Lenin's Choice
The first public reaction to the idea of reactualizing
Lenin is, of course, an outburst of sarcastic laughter: Marx is OK,
even on Wall Street, there are people who love him today
- Marx the poet of commodities, who provided perfect descriptions
of the capitalist dynamics, Marx of the Cultural Studies, who portrayed
the alienation and reification of our daily lives -, but Lenin, no,
you can't be serious! The working class movement, revolutionary Party,
and similar zombie-concepts? Doesn't Lenin stand precisely for the
FAILURE to put Marxism into practice, for the big catastrophe which
left its mark on the entire XXth century world politics, for the Real
Socialist experiment which culminated in an economically inefficient
dictatorship? So, in the contemporary academic politics, the idea
to deal with Lenin is accompanied by two qualifications: yes, why
not, we live in a liberal democracy, there is freedom of thought...
however, one should treat Lenin in an "objective critical and
scientific way," not in an attitude of nostalgic idolatry, and,
furthermore, from the perspective firmly rooted in the democratic
political order, within the horizon of human rights - therein resides
the lesson painfully learned through the experience of the XXth century
totalitarianisms.
What are we to say to this? Again, the problem resides in the implicit
qualifications which can be easily discerned by the "concrete
analysis of the concrete situation," as Lenin himself would have
put it. "Fidelity to the democratic consensus" means the
acceptance of the present liberal-parlamentary consensus, which precludes
any serious questioning of how this liberal-democratic order is complicit
in the phenomena it officially condemns, and, of course, any serious
attempt to imagine a society whose socio-political order would be
different. In short, it means: say and write whatever you want - on
condition that what you do does not effectively question or disturb
the predominant political consensus. So everything is allowed, solicited
even, as a critical topic: the prospects of a global ecological catastrophe,
violations of human rights, sexism, homophobia, antifeminism, the
growing violence not only in the far-away countries, but also in our
megalopolises, the gap between the First and the Third World, between
the rich and the poor, the shattering impact of the digitalization
of our daily lives... there is nothing easier today than to get international,
state or corporate funds for a multidisciplinary research into how
to fight the new forms of ethnic, religious or sexist violence. The
problem is that all this occurs against the background of a fundamental
Denkverbot, the prohibition to think. Today's liberal-democratic hegemony
is sustained by a kind of unwritten Denkverbot similar to the infamous
Berufsverbot in Germany of the late 60s - the moment one shows a minimal
sign of engaging in political projects that aim to seriously challenge
the existing order, the answer is immediately: "Benevolent as
it is, this will necessarily end in a new Gulag!" The ideological
function of the constant reference to the holocaust, gulag and the
more recent Third World catastrophes is thus to serve as the support
of this Denkverbot by constantly reminding us how things may have
been much worse: "Just look around and see for yourself what
will happen if we follow your radical notions!" And it is exactly
the same thing that the demand for "scientific objectivity"
means: the moment one seriously questions the existing liberal consensus,
one is accused of abandoning scientific objectivity for the outdated
ideological positions. This is the point on which one cannot and should
not concede: today, the actual freedom of thought means the freedom
to question the predominant liberal-democratic "post-ideological"
consensus - or it means nothing.
Habermas designated the present era as that of the neue Undurchsichtlichkeit
- the new opacity.1 More than ever, our daily experience is mystifying:
modernization generates new obscurantisms, the reduction of freedom
is presented to us as the arrival of new freedoms. In these circumstances,
one should be especially careful not to confuse the ruling ideology
with ideology which SEEMS to dominate. More then ever, one should
bear in mind Walter Benjamin's reminder that it is not enough to ask
how a certain theory (or art) declares itself to stay with regard
to social struggles - one should also ask how it effectively functions
IN these very struggles. In sex, the effectively hegemonic attitude
is not patriarchal repression, but free promiscuity; in art, provocations
in the style of the notorious "Sensation" exhibitions ARE
the norm, the example of the art fully integrated into the establishment.
One is therefore tempted to turn around Marx's thesis 11: the first
task today is precisely NOT to succumb to the temptation to act, to
directly intervene and change things (which then inevitably ends in
a cul de sac of debilitating impossibility: "what can one do
against the global capital?"), but to question the hegemonic
ideological coordinates. If, today, one follows a direct call to act,
this act will not be performed in an empty space - it will be an act
WITHIN the hegemonic ideological coordinates: those who "really
want to do something to help people" get involved in (undoubtedly
honorable) exploits like Medecins sans frontiere, Greenpeace, feminist
and anti-racist campaigns, which are all not only tolerated, but even
supported by the media, even if they seemingly enter the economic
territory (say, denouncing and boycotting companies which do not respect
ecological conditions or which use child labor) - they are tolerated
and supported as long as they do not get too close to a certain limit.
This kind of activity provides the perfect example of interpassivity2:
of doing things not to achieve something, but to PREVENT from something
really happening, really changing. All the frenetic humanitarian,
politically correct, etc., activity fits the formula of "Let's
go on changing something all the time so that, globally, things will
remain the same!"
Let us take two predominant topics of today's American radical academia:
postcolonial and queer (gay) studies. The problem of postcolonialism
is undoubtedly crucial; however, "postcolonial studies"
tend to translate it into the multiculturalist problematic of the
colonized minorities' "right to narrate" their victimizing
experience, of the power mechanisms which repress "otherness,"
so that, at the end of the day, we learn that the root of the postcolonial
exploitation is our intolerance towards the Other, and, furthermore,
that this intolerance itself is rooted in our intolerance towards
the "Stranger in Ourselves," in our inability to confront
what we repressed in and of ourselves - the politico-economic struggle
is thus imperceptibly transformed into a pseudo-psychoanalytic drama
of the subject unable to confront its inner traumas... The true corruption
of the American academia is not primarily financial, it is not only
that they are able to buy many European critical intellectuals (myself
included - up to a point), but conceptual: notions of the "European"
critical theory are imperceptibly translated into the benign universe
of the Cultural Studies chic.
My personal experience is that practically all of the "radical"
academics silently count on the long-term stability of the American
capitalist model, with the secure tenured position as their ultimate
professional goal (a surprising number of them even play on the stock
market). If there is a thing they are genuinely horrified of, it is
a radical shattering of the (relatively) safe life environment of
the "symbolic classes" in the developed Western societies.
Their excessive Politically Correct zeal when dealing with sexism,
racism, Third World sweatshops, etc., is thus ultimately a defense
against their own innermost identification, a kind of compulsive ritual
whose hidden logic is: "Let's talk as much as possible about
the necessity of a radical change to make it sure that nothing will
really change!" Symptomatic is here the journal October: when
you ask one of the editors to what the title refers, they will half-confidentially
signal that it is, of course, THAT October - in this way, one can
indulge in the jargonistic analyses of the modern art, with the hidden
assurance that one is somehow retaining the link with the radical
revolutionary past... With regard to this radical chic, the first
gesture towards the Third Way ideologists and practitioners should
be that of praise: they at least play their game in a straight way,
and are honest in their acceptance of the global capitalist coordinates,
in contrast to the pseudo-radical academic Leftists who adopt towards
the Third Way the attitude of utter disdain, while their own radicality
ultimately amounts to an empty gesture which obliges no one to anything
determinate.
It is true that, today, it is the radical populist Right which is
usually breaking the (still) predominant liberal-democratic consensus,
gradually rendering acceptable the hitherto excluded topics (the partial
justification of Fascism, the need to constrain abstract citizenship
on behalf of ethnic identity, etc.). However, the hegemonic liberal
democracy is using this fact to blackmail the Left radicals: "we
shouldn't play with fire: against the new Rightist onslaught, one
should more than ever insist on the democratic consensus - any criticism
of it willingly or unwillingly helps the new Right!" This is
the key line of separation: one should reject this blackmail, taking
the risk of disturbing the liberal consensus, up to questioning the
very notion of democracy.
So how are we to respond to the eternal dilemma of the radical Left:
should one strategical support center-Left figures like Bill Clinton
against the conservatives, or should one adopt the stance of "it
doesn't matter, we shouldn't get involved in these fights - in a way,
it is even better if the Right is directly in power, since, in this
way, it will be easier for the people to see the truth of the situation"?
The answer is the variation of old Stalin's answer to the question
"Which deviation is worse, the Rightist or the Leftist one?":
THEY ARE BOTH WORSE. What one should do is to adopt the stance of
the proper dialectical paradox: in principle, of course, one should
be indifferent towards the struggle between the liberal and conservative
pole of today's official politics - however, one can only afford to
be indifferent if the liberal option is in power. Otherwise, the price
to be paid may appear much too high - recall the catastrophic consequences
of the decision of the German Communist Party in the early 30s NOT
to focus on the struggle against the Nazis, with the justification
that the Nazi dictatorship is the last desperate stage of the capitalist
domination, which will open eyes to the working class, shattering
their belief in the "bourgeois" democratic institutions.
Along these lines, Claude Lefort himself, whom no one can accuse of
communist sympathies, recently made a crucial point in his answer
to Francois Furet: today's liberal consensus is the result of 150
years of the Leftist workers' struggle and pressure upon the State,
it incorporated demands which were 100 or even less years ago dismissed
by liberals as horror.3 As a proof, one should just look at the list
of the demands at the end of the Communist Manifesto: apart from 2
or 3 of them (which, of course, are the key one), all others are today
part of the consensus (at least the disintegrating Welfare State one):
the universal vote, the right to free education, universal healthcare
and care for the retired, limitation of child labor...
Interpretation versus Formalization
So where are we to begin? In the present climate of the New Age obscurantism,
it may appear attractive to reassert the lesson of Lenin's Materialism
and Empiriocriticism: in today's popular reading of quantum physics,
as in Lenin's times, the doxa is that science itself finally overcame
materialism - matter is supposed to "disappear," to dissolve
in the immaterial waves of energy fields.4 It is also true (as Lucio
Colletti emphasized), that Lenin's distinction between the philosophical
and the scientific notion of matter, according to which, since the
philosophical notion of matter as reality existing independently of
mind precludes any intervention of philosophy into sciences, the very
notion of "dialectics in/of nature" is thoroughly undermined.
However... the "however" concerns the fact that, in Materialism
and Empiriocriticism, there is NO PLACE FOR DIALECTICS, FOR HEGEL.
What are Lenin's basic theses? The rejection to reduce knowledge to
phenomenalist or pragmatic instrumentalism (i.e., the assertion that,
in scientific knowledge, we get to know the way things exist independently
of our minds - the infamous "theory of reflection"), coupled
with the insistence of the precarious nature of our knowledge (which
is always limited, relative, and "reflects" external reality
only in the infinite process of approximation). Does this not sound
familiar? Is this, in the Anglo-Saxon tradition of analytical philosophy,
not the basic position of Karl Popper, the archetypal anti-Hegelian?
In his short article "Lenin and Popper,"5 Colletti recalls
how, in a private letter from 1970, first published in Die Zeit, Popper
effectively wrote: "Lenin's book on empiriocriticism is, in my
opinion, truly excellent."6
This hard materialist core of Empiriocriticism persists in the Philosophical
Note-Books from 1915, in spite of Lenin's rediscovery of Hegel - why?
In his Note-Books, Lenin is struggling with the same problem as Adorno
in his "negative dialectics": how to combine Hegel's legacy
of the critique of every immediacy, of the subjective mediation of
all given objectivity, with the minimum of materialism that Adorno
calls the "predominance of the objective" (this is the reason
why Lenin still clings to the "theory of reflection" according
to which the human thought mirrors objective reality).7 However, both
Adorno and Lenin take here the wrong path: the way to assert materialism
is not by way of clinging to the minimum of objective reality OUTSIDE
the thought's subjective mediation, but by insisting on the absolute
INHERENCE of the external obstacle which prevents thought from attaining
full identity with itself. The moment we concede on this point and
externalize the obstacle, we regress to the pseudo-problematic of
the thought asymptotically approaching the ever-elusive "objective
reality," never being able to grasp it in it infinite complexity.8
The problem with Lenin's "theory of reflection" resides
in its implicit idealism: its very compulsive insistence on the independent
existence of the material reality outside consciousness is to be read
as a symptomatic displacement, destined to conceal the key fact that
the consciousness itself is implicitly posited as EXTERNAL to the
reality it "reflects." The very metaphor of the infinite
approaching to the way things really are, to the objective truth,
betrays this idealism: what this metaphor leaves out of consideration
is the fact that the partiality (distortion) of the "subjective
reflection" occurs precisely because the subject is INCLUDED
in the process it reflects - only a consciousness observing the universe
from without would see the whole of reality "the way it really
is."9
This, of course, in no way entails that the tracing of the difference
between idealism and materialism is today not more crucial than ever:
one should only proceed in a truly Leninist way, discerning - through
the "concrete analysis of concrete circumstances" - WHERE
this line of separation runs. One is thus tempted to claim that, even
WITHIN the field of religion, the singular point of the emergence
of materialism is signalled by Christ's words on the cross "Father,
why have you forsaken me?" - in this moment of total abandonment,
the subject experiences and fully assumes the inexistence of the big
Other. More generally, the line of division is that between the "idealist"
Socratic-Gnostic tradition claiming that the truth is within us, just
to be (re)discovered through an inner journey, and the Judeo-Christian
"materialist" notion that truth can only emerge from an
EXTERNAL traumatic encounter which shatters the subject's balance.
"Truth" requires an effort in which we have to fight our
"spontaneous" tendency.
And what if we were to connect this notion of the truth emerging from
an external encounter with the (in)famous Lenin's notion, from What
Is to Be Done?, of how the working class cannot achieve its adequate
class consciousness "spontaneously," through its own "organic"
development, i.e. of how this truth has to be introduced into it from
outside (by the Party intellectuals)? In quoting Kautsky at this place,
Lenin makes a significant change in his paraphrase: while Kautsky
speaks of how the non-working-class intellectuals, who are OUTSIDE
THE CLASS STRUGGLE, should introduce SCIENCE (providing objective
knowledge of history) to the working class, Lenin speaks of CONSCIOUSNESS
which should be introduced from outside by intellectuals who are outside
the ECONOMIC struggle, NOT outside the class struggle! Here is the
passage from Kautsky which Lenin quotes approvingly -
"/.../ socialism and class struggle arise side by side and not
one out of the other; each arises under different conditions. /.../
The vehicle of science is not the proletariat, but the bourgeois intelligentsia
/.../ Thus, socialist consciousness is something introduced into the
proletarian class struggle from without and not something that arose
within it spontaneously."10
- and here is Lenin's paraphrase of it:
" /.../ all worship of the spontaneity of the working-class movement,
all belittling of the role of 'the conscious element,' of the role
of Social-Democracy, means, quite independently of whether he who
belittles that role desires it or not, a strengthening of the influence
of bourgeois ideology upon workers. /.../ the only choice is - either
bourgeois or socialist ideology. There is no middle course /.../ the
spontaneous development of the working-class movement leads to its
subordination to bourgeois ideology /.../ for the spontaneous working-class
movement is trade-unionism."11
It may SOUND the same, but it's NOT: in Kautsky, there is no space
for politics proper, just the combination of the social (working class
and its struggle, from which intellectuals are implicitly EXCLUDED)
and the pure neutral classless, asubjective, knowledge of these intellectuals.
In Lenin, on the contrary, "intellectuals" themselves are
caught in the conflict of IDEOLOGIES (i.e. the ideological class struggle)
which is unsurpassable. (It was already Marx who made this point,
from his youth when he dreamt of the unity of German Idealist philosophy
and the French revolutionary masses, to his insistence, in late years,
that the leadership of the International should under no conditions
be left to the English workers: although the most numerous and best
organized, they - in contrast to German workers - lack theoretical
stringency.)
The key question thus concerns the exact STATUS of this externality:
is it simply the externality of an impartial "objective"
scientist who, after studying history and establishing that, in the
long run, the working class has a great future ahead, decides to join
the winning side? So when Lenin says "The theory of Marx is all-powerful,
because it is true," everything depends on how we understand
"truth" here: is it a neutral "objective knowledge,"
or the truth of an engaged subject? Lenin's wager - today, in our
era of postmodern relativism, more actual than ever - is that universal
truth and partisanship, the gesture of taking sides, are not only
not mutually exclusive, but condition each other: in a concrete situation,
its UNIVERSAL truth can only be articulated from a thoroughly PARTISAN
position - truth is by definition one-sided. (This, of course, goes
against the predominant doxa of compromise, of finding a middle path
among the multitude of conflicting interests.) Why not, then, shamelessly
and courageously ENDORSE the boring standard reproach according to
which, Marxism is a "secularized religion," with Lenin as
the Messiah, etc.? Yes, assuming the proletarian standpoint IS EXACTLY
like making a leap of faith and assuming a full subjective engagement
for its Cause; yes, the "truth" of Marxism is perceptible
only to those who accomplish this leap, NOT to any neutral observers.
What the EXTERNALITY means here is that this truth is nonetheless
UNIVERSAL, not just the "point-of-view" of a particular
historical subject: "external" intellectuals are needed
because the working class cannot immediately perceive ITS OWN PLACE
within the social totality which enables it to accomplish its "mission"
- this insight has to be mediated through an external element.
And why not link these two externalities (that of the traumatic experience
of the divine Real, and that of the Party) to the third one, that
of the ANALYST in the psychoanalytic cure? In all three cases, we
are dealing with the same impossibility which bears witness to a materialist
obstacle: it is not possible for the believer to "discover God
in himself," through self-immersion, by spontaneously realizing
its own Self - God must intervene from outside, disturbing our balance;
it is not possible for the working class to actualize spontaneously
its historical mission - the Party must intervene from outside, shaking
it out of its self-indulgent spontaneity; it is not possible for the
patient/analyst to analyze himself - in contrast to the Gnostic self-immersion,
in psychoanalysis, there is no self-analysis proper, analysis is only
possible if a foreign kernel which gives body to the object-cause
of the subject's desire. Why, then, this impossibility? Precisely
because neither of the three subjects (believer, proletarian, analyst)
is a self-centered agent of self-mediation, but a decentered agent
struggling with a foreign kernel. God, Analyst, Party - the three
forms of the "subject supposed to know," of the transferential
object, which is why, in all three cases, one hears the claim "God/Analyst/
the Party is always right"; and, as it was clear already to Kierkegaard,
the truth of this statement is always its negative - MAN is always
wrong. This external element does not stand for objective knowledge,
i.e. its externality is strictly INTERNAL: the need for the Party
stems from the fact that the working class is never "fully itself."
In his Introduction to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right,
Marx already deploys something like the logic of hegemony: the emergence
of a "universal class," a particular class which imposes
itself as universal, engendering global enthusiasm, standing for society
AS SUCH against the ancien regime, anti-social crime AS SUCH (like
bourgeoisie in the French revolution). After follows the disillusion
so sarcastically described by Marx: the day after, the gap between
universal and particular becomes visible again, capitalist vulgar
profit as the actuality of universal freedom, etc. - For Marx, of
course, the only universal class whose singularity (exclusion from
society of property) guarantees its ACTUAL universality, is the proletariat.
This is what Ernesto Laclau rejects in his logic of hegemony: for
Laclau, the short-circuit between the Universal and the Particular
is ALWAYS illusory, temporary, a kind of "transcendental paralogism."12
However, is Marx's proletariat really the negative of positive full
essential humanity, or "only" the gap of universality AS
SUCH, irrecoverable in any positivity?13 In Alain Badiou's terms,
proletariat is not another PARTICULAR class, but a SINGULARITY of
the social structure, and AS SUCH the universal class, the non-class
among the classes.
What is crucial here is the properly temporal-dialectical tension
between the Universal and the Particular. When Marx says that, in
Germany, because of the compromised pettiness of the bourgeoisie,
it is too late for the partial bourgeois emancipation, and that, because
of it, in Germany, the condition of every particular emancipation
is the UNIVERSAL emancipation, one way to read this is to see in it
the assertion of the universal "normal" paradigm and its
exception: in the "normal" case, partial (false) bourgeois
emancipation will be followed by the universal emancipation through
the proletarian revolution, while in Germany, the "normal"
order gets mixed up. There is, however, another, much more radical
way to read it: the very German exception, the inability of its bourgeoisie
to achieve partial emancipation, opens up the space for the possible
UNIVERSAL emancipation. The dimension of universality thus emerges
(only) where the "normal" order enchaining the succession
of the particulars is perturbed. Because of this, there is no "normal"
revolution, EACH revolutionary explosion is grounded in an exception,
in a short-circuit of "too late" and "too early."
The French Revolution occurred because France was not able to follow
the "normal" English path of capitalist development; the
very "normal" English path resulted in the "unnatural"
division of labor between the capitalists who hold socio-economic
power and the aristocracy to which was left the political power.
One can also make the same point in the terms of the opposition between
interpretation and formalization14: the external agent (Party, God,
Analyst) is NOT the one who "understands us better than ourselves,"
who can provide the true interpretation of what our acts and statements
mean; it rather stands for the FORM of our activity. Say, Marx's deployment
of the commodity form in the Chapter 1 of Capital is NOT a "narrative,"
a Vorstellung, but a Darstellung, the deployment of the inner structure
of the universe of merchandises - the narrative is, on the contrary,
the story of the "primitive accumulation," the myth capitalism
proposes about its own origins. (Along the same lines, Hegel's Phenomenology
- contrary to Rorty's reading - does not propose a large narrative,
but the FORM of subjectivity; as Hegel himself emphasizes in the Foreword,
it focuses on the "formal aspect /das Formelle/.15 This is how
one should approach the absence of large all-encompassing narratives
today - recall Fredric Jameson's supple description of the deadlock
of the dialogue between the Western New Left and the Eastern European
dissidents, of the absence of any common language between them:
"To put it briefly, the East wishes to talk in terms of power
and oppression; the West in terms of culture and commodification.
There are really no common denominators in this initial struggle for
discursive rules, and what we end up with is the inevitable comedy
of each side muttering irrelevant replies in its own favorite language."16
Jameson at the same time insists that Marxism still provides the universal
meta-language enabling us to situate and relate all other partial
narrativizations/interpretations - is he simply inconsistent? Are
there two Jamesons: one, postmodern, the theorist of the irreducible
multiplicity of the narratives, the other, the more traditional partisan
of the Marxist universal hermeneutics? The only way to save Jameson
from this predicament is to insist that Marxism is here not the all-encompassing
interpretive horizon, but the matrix which enables us to account for
(to generate) the multiplicity of narratives and/or interpretations.
It is also here that one should introduce the key dialectical distinction
between the FOUNDING figure of a movement and the later figure who
FORMALIZED this movement: ultimately, it was Lenin who effectively
"formalized" Marx by way of defining the Party as the political
form of its historical intervention, in the same way that St. Paul
"formalized" Christ and Lacan "formalized" Freud.17
This formalization is strictly correlative to focusing on the Real
of an antagonism: "class struggle" is not the last horizon
of meaning, the last signified of all social phenomena, but the formal
generative matrix of the different ideological horizons of understanding.
That is to say, one should not confuse this properly dialectical notion
of Form with the liberal-multiculturalist notion of Form as the neutral
framework of the multitude of "narratives" - not only literature,
but also politics, religion, science, they are all different narratives,
stories we are telling ourselves about ourselves, and the ultimate
goal of ethics is to guarantee the neutral space in which this multitude
of narratives can peacefully coexist, in which everyone, from ethnic
to sexual minorities, will have the right and possibility to tell
his story. The properly dialectical notion of Form signals precisely
the IMPOSSIBILITY of this liberal notion of Form: Form has nothing
to do with "formalism," with the idea of a neutral Form,
independent of its contingent particular content; it rather stands
for the traumatic kernel of the Real, for the antagonism, which "colors"
the entire field in question. In this precise sense, class struggle
is the Form of the Social: every social phenomenon is overdetermined
by it, which means that it is not possible to remain neutral towards
it.
Of Apes and Men
Lenin's legacy to be reinvented today is the politics of truth. We
live in the "postmodern" era in which truth-claims as such
are dismissed as an expression of hidden power-mechanisms - as the
reborn pseudo-Nietzscheans like to emphasize, truth is a lie which
is most efficient in asserting our will to power. The very question,
apropos of some statement, "Is it true?", is supplanted
by the question "Under what power conditions can this statement
be uttered?". What we get instead of the universal truth is the
multitude of perspectives, or, as it is fashionable to put it today,
of "narratives" - not only literature, but also politics,
religion, science, they are all different narratives, stories we are
telling ourselves about ourselves, and the ultimate goal of ethics
is to guarantee the neutral space in which this multitude of narratives
can peacefully coexist, in which everyone, from ethnic to sexual minorities,
will have the right and possibility to tell his story. THE two philosophers
of today's global capitalism are the two great Left-liberal "progressives,"
Richard Rorty and Peter Singer - honest in their consequent stance.
Rorty defines the basic coordinates: the fundamental dimension of
a human being is the ability to suffer, to experience pain and humiliation
- consequently, since humans are symbolic animals, the fundamental
right is the right to narrate one's experience of suffering and humiliation.18
Singer then provides the Darwinian background.19
Singer - usually designated as a "social Darwinist with a collectivist
socialist face" - starts innocently enough, trying to argue that
people will be happier if they lead lives committed to ethics: a life
spent trying to help others and reduce suffering is really the most
moral and fulfilling one. He radicalizes and actualizes Jeremiah Bentham,
the father of utilitarianism: the ultimate ethical criterion is not
the dignity (rationality, soul) of man, but the ability to SUFFER,
to experience pain, which man shares with animals. With inexorable
radicality, Singer levels the animal/human divide: better kill an
old suffering woman that healthy animals... Look an orangutan straight
in the eye and what do you see? A none-too-distant cousin - a creature
worthy of all the legal rights and privileges that humans enjoy. One
should thus extend aspects of equality - the right to life, the protection
of individual liberties, the prohibition of torture - at least to
the nonhuman great apes (chimpanzees, orangutans, gorillas).
Singer argues that "speciesism" (privileging the human species)
is no different from racism: our perception of a difference between
humans and (other) animals is no less illogical and unethical than
our one-time perception of an ethical difference between, say, men
and women, or blacks and whites. Intelligence is no basis for determining
ethical stature: the lives of humans are not worth more than the lives
of animals simply because they display more intelligence (if intelligence
were a standard of judgment, Singer points out, we could perform medical
experiments on the mentally retarded with moral impunity). Ultimately,
all things being equal, an animal has as much interest in living as
a human. Therefore, all things being equal, medical experimentation
on animals is immoral: those who advocate such experiments claim that
sacrificing the lives of 20 animals will save millions of human lives
- however, what about sacrificing 20 humans to save millions of animals?
As Singer's critics like to point out, the horrifying extension of
this principle is that the interests of 20 people outweighs the interests
of one, which gives the green light to all sorts of human rights abuses.
Consequently, Singer argues that we can no longer rely on traditional
ethics for answers to the dilemmas which our constellation imposes
on ourselves; he proposes a new ethics meant to protect the quality,
not the sanctity, of human life. As sharp boundaries disappear between
life and death, between humans and animals, this new ethics casts
doubt on the morality of animal research, while offering a sympathetic
assessment of infanticide. When a baby is born with severe defects
of the sort that always used to kill babies, are doctors and parents
now morally obligated to use the latest technologies, regardless of
cost? NO. When a pregnant woman loses all brain function, should doctors
use new procedures to keep her body living until the baby can be born?
NO. Can a doctor ethically help terminally ill patients to kill themselves?
YES.
The first thing to discern here is the hidden utopian dimension of
such a survivalist stance. The easiest way to detect ideological surplus-enjoyment
in an ideological formation is to read it as a dream and analyze the
displacement at work in it. Freud reports of a dream of one of his
patients which consists of a simple scene: the patient is at a funeral
of one of his relatives. The key to the dream (which repeats a real-life
event from the previous day) is that, at this funeral, the patient
unexpectedly encountered a woman, his old love towards whom he still
felt very deeply - far from being a masochistic dream, this dream
thus simply articulates the patient's joy at meeting again his old
love. Is the mechanism of displacement at work in this dream not strictly
homologous to the one elaborated by Fredric Jameson apropos of a science-fiction
film which takes place in California in near future, after a mysterious
virus has very quickly killed a great majority of the population?
When the film's heroes wander in the empty shopping malls, with all
the merchandises intact at their disposal, is this libidinal gain
of having access to the material goods without the alienating market
machinery not the true point of the film occluded by the displacement
of the official focus of the narrative on the catastrophe caused by
the virus? At an even more elementary level, is not one of the commonplaces
of the sci-fi theory that the true point of the novels or movies about
a global catastrophe resides in the sudden reassertion of social solidarity
and the spirit of collaboration among the survivors? It is as if,
in our society, global catastrophe is the price one has to pay for
gaining access to solidary collaboration...
When my son was a small boy, his most cherished personal possession
was a special large "survival knife" whose handle contained
a compass, a sack of powder to disinfect water, a fishing hook and
line, and other similar items - totally useless in our social reality,
but perfectly fitting the survivalist fantasy of finding oneself alone
in wild nature. It is this same fantasy which, perhaps, give the clue
to the success of Joshua Piven's and David Borgenicht's surprise best-seller
The Worst-Case Scenario Survival Handbook.20 Suffice it to mention
two supreme examples from it: What to do if an alligator has its jaws
closed on your limb? (Answer: you should tap or punch it on the snout,
because alligators automatically react to it by opening their mouths.)
What to do if you confront a lion which threatens to attack you? (Answer:
try to make yourself appear bigger than you are by opening your coat
wide.) The joke of the book thus consists in the discord between its
enunciated content and its position of enunciation: the situations
it describes are effectively serious and the solutions correct - the
only problem is WHY IS THE AUTHOR TELLING US ALL THIS? WHO NEEDS THIS
ADVICE?
The underlying irony is that, in our individualistic competitive society,
the most useless advice concerns survival in extreme physical situations
- what one effectively needs is the very opposite, the Dale Carnegie
type of books which tell us how to win over (manipulate) other people:
the situations rendered in The Worst-Case Scenario lack any symbolic
dimension, they reduce us to pure survival machines. In short, The
Worst-Case Scenario became a best-seller for the very same reason
Sebastian Junger's The Perfect Storm, the story (and the movie) about
the struggle for survival of a fishing vessel caught in the "storm
of the century" east of the Canadian coast in 1991, became one:
they both stage the fantasy of the pure encounter with a natural threat
in which the socio-symbolic dimension is suspended. In a way, The
Perfect Storm even provides the secret utopian background of The Worst-Case
Scenario: it is only in such extreme situations that an authentic
intersubjective community, held together by solidarity, can emerge.
Let us not forget that The Perfect Storm is ultimately the book about
the solidarity of a small working class collective! The humorous appeal
of The Worst-Case Scenario can thus be read as bearing witness to
our utter alienation from nature, exemplified by the shortage of contact
with "real life" dangers.
We all know the standard pragmatic-utilitarian criticism of the abstract
humanist education: who needs philosophy, Latin quotes, classic literature
- one should rather learn how to act and produce in real life... well,
in The Worst-Case Scenario, we get such real life lessons, with the
result that they uncannily resemble the useless classic humanist education.
Recall the proverbial scenes of the drilling of young pupils, boring
them to death by making them mechanically repeat some formulas (like
the declination of the Latin verbs) - the Worst-Case Scenario counterpoint
to it would have been the scene of forcing the small children in the
elementary school to learn by heart the answers to the predicaments
this book describes by repeating them mechanically after the teacher:
"When the alligator bites your leg, you punch him on the nose
with your hand! When the lion confronts you, you open your coat wide!"21
So, back to Singer, one cannot dismiss him as a monstrous exaggeration
- what Adorno said about psychoanalysis (its truth resides in its
very exaggerations)22 fully holds for Singer: he is so traumatic and
intolerable because his scandalous "exaggerations" directly
renders visible the truth of the so-called postmodern ethics. Is effectively
not the ultimate horizon of the postmodern "identity politics"
Darwinian - defending the right of some particular species of the
humankind within the panoply of their proliferating multitude (gays
with AIDS, black single mothers...)? The very opposition between "conservative"
and "progressive" politics can be conceived of in the terms
of Darwinism: ultimately, conservatives defend the right of those
with might (their very success proves that they won in the struggle
for survival), while progressives advocate the protection of endangered
human species, i.e., of those losing the struggle for survival.23
One of the divisions in the chapter on Reason in Hegel's Phenomenology
of Spirit speaks about "das geistige Tierreich" (the spiritual
animal kingdom): the social world which lacks any spiritual substance,
so that, in it, individuals effectively interact as "intelligent
animals." They use reason, but only in order to assert their
individual interests, to manipulate others into serving their own
pleasures.24 Is not a world in which the highest rights are human
rights precisely such a "spiritual animal kingdom," a universe?
There is, however, a price to be paid for such liberation - in such
a universe, human rights ultimately function as ANIMAL rights. This,
then, is the ultimate truth of Singer: our universe of human right
is the universe of animal rights.
The obvious counterargument is here: so what? Why should we not reduce
humankind to its proper place, that of one of the animal species?
What gets lost in this reduction? Jacques-Alain Miller, the main pupil
of Jacques Lacan, once commented an uncanny laboratory experiment
with rats25: in a labyrinthine set-up, a desired object (a piece of
good food or a sexual partner) is first made easily accessible to
a rat; then, the set-up is changed in such a way that the rat sees
and thereby knows where the desired object is, but cannot gain access
to it; in exchange for it, as a kind of consolation prize, a series
of similar objects of inferior value is made easily accessible - how
does the rat react to it? For some time, it tries to find its way
to the "true" object; then, upon ascertaining that this
object is definitely out of reach, the rat will renounce it and put
up with some of the inferior substitute objects - in short, it will
act as a "rational" subject of utilitarianism.
It is only now, however, that the true experiment begins: the scientists
performed a surgical operation on the rat, messing about with its
brain, doing things to it with laser beams about which, as Miller
put it delicately, it is better to know nothing. So what happened
when the operated rat was again let loose in the labyrinth, the one
in which the "true" object is inaccessible? The rat insisted:
it never became fully reconciled with the loss of the "true"
object and resigned itself to one of the inferior substitutes, but
repeatedly returned to it, attempted to reach it. In short, the rat
in a sense was humanized; it assumed the tragic "human"
relationship towards the unattainable absolute object which, on account
of its very inaccessibility, forever captivates our desire. On the
other hand, it is this very "conservative" fixation that
pushes man to continuing renovation, since he never can fully integrate
this excess into his life process. So we can see why did Freud use
the term Todestrieb: the lesson of psychoanalysis is that humans are
not simply alive; on the top of it, they are possessed by a strange
drive to enjoy life in excess of the ordinary run of things - and
"death" stands simply and precisely for the dimension beyond
ordinary biological life.
This, then, is what gets lost in Singer's "geistige Tierreich":
the Thing, something to which we are unconditionally attached irrespective
of its positive qualities. In Singer's universe, there is a place
for mad cows, but no place for an Indian sacred cow. In, in other
words, what gets lost here is simply the dimension of truth - NOT
"objective truth" as the notion of reality from a point
of view which somehow floats above the multitude of particular narratives,
but truth as the Singular Universal." When Lenin said "The
theory of Marx is all-powerful, because it is true," everything
depends on how we understand "truth" here: is it a neutral
"objective knowledge," or the truth of an engaged subject?
Lenin's wager - today, in our era of postmodern relativism, more actual
than ever - is that universal truth and partisanship, the gesture
of taking sides, are not only not mutually exclusive, but condition
each other: in a concrete situation, its UNIVERSAL truth can only
be articulated from a thoroughly PARTISAN position - truth is by definition
one-sided. This, of course, goes against the predominant doxa of compromise,
of finding a middle path among the multitude of conflicting interests.
If one does not specify the CRITERIA of the different, alternate,
narrativization, then this endeavor courts the danger of endorsing,
in the Politically Correct mood, ridiculous "narratives"
like those about the supremacy of some aboriginal holistic wisdom,
of dismissing science as just another narrative on a par with premodern
superstitions. The Leninist narrative to the postmodern multiculturalist
"right to narrate" should thus be an unashamed assertion
of the right to truth. When, in the debacle of 1914, all European
Social Democratic parties (with the honorable exception of the Russian
Bolsheviks and the Serb Social Democrats) succumbed to the war fervor
and voted for the military credits, Lenin's thorough rejection of
the "patriotic line," in its very isolation from the predominant
mood, designated the singular emergence of the truth of the entire
situation.
In a closer analysis, one should exhibit how the cultural relativism
of the "right-to-narrate" orientation contains its own apparent
opposite, the fixation on the Real of some trauma which resists its
narrativization. This properly dialectical tension sustains today's
the academic "holocaust industry." My own ultimate experience
of the holocaust-industry police occurred in 1997 at a round table
in the Centre Pompidou in Paris: I was viciously attacked for an intervention
in which (among other things) I claimed, against the neoconservatives
deploring the decline of faith today, that the basic need of a normal
human being is not to believe himself, but to have another subject
who will believe for him, at his place - the reaction of one of the
distinguished participants was that, by claiming this, I am ultimately
endorsing the holocaust revisionism, justifying the claim that, since
everything is a discursive construct, this includes also the holocaust,
so it is meaningless to search for what really happened there... Apart
from displaying a hypocritical paranoia, my critic was doubly wrong:
first, the holocaust revisionists (to my knowledge) NEVER argue in
the terms of the postmodern discursive constructionism, but in the
terms of very empirical factual analysis: their claims range from
the "fact" that there is no written document in which Hitler
would have ordered the holocaust, to the weird mathematics of "taking
into account the number of gas ovens in Auschwitz, it was not possible
to burn so many corpses." Furthermore, not only is the postmodern
logic of "everything is a discursive construction, there are
no direct firm facts" NEVER used to deflate the holocaust; in
a paradox worth noting, it is precisely the postmodern discursive
constructionists (like Lyotard) who tend to elevate the holocaust
into the supreme ineffable metaphysical Evil - the holocaust serves
them as the untouchable-sacred Real, as the negative of the contingent
language games.26
The problem with those who perceive every comparison between the holocaust
and other concentration camps and mass political crimes as an inadmissible
relativization of the holocaust, is that they miss the point and display
their own doubt: yes, the holocaust WAS unique, but the only way to
establish this uniqueness is to compare it with other similar phenomena
and thus demonstrate the limit of this comparison. If one does not
risk this comparison, of one prohibits it, one gets caught in the
Wittgensteinian paradox of prohibiting to speak about that about which
we cannot speak: if we stick to the prohibition of the comparison,
the gnawing suspicion emerges that, if we were to be allowed to compare
the holocaust with other similar crimes, it would be deprived of its
uniqueness...
Lenin As a Listener of Schubert
So how can the reference to Lenin deliver us from this stuff predicament?
Some libertarian Leftists want to redeem - partially, at least - Lenin
by opposing the "bad" Jacobin-elitist Lenin of What Is To
Be Done?, relying on the Party as the professional intellectual elite
which enlightens the working class from OUTSIDE, and the "good"
Lenin of State and Revolution, who envisioned the prospect of abolishing
the State, of the broad masses directly taking into their hands the
administration of the public affairs. However, this opposition has
its limits: the key premise of State and Revolution is that one cannot
fully "democratize" the State, that State "as such,"
in its very notion, is a dictatorship of one class over another; the
logical conclusion from this premise is that, insofar as we still
dwell within the domain of the State, we are legitimized to exercise
full violent terror, since, within this domain, every democracy is
a fake. So, since state is an instrument of oppression, it is not
worth trying to improve its apparatuses, the protection of the legal
order, elections, laws guaranteeing personal freedoms... - all this
becomes irrelevant. The moment of truth in this reproach is that one
cannot separate the unique constellation which enabled the revolutionary
takeover in October 1917 from its later "Stalinist" turn:
the very constellation that rendered the revolution possible (peasants'
dissatisfaction, a well-organized revolutionary elite, etc.) led to
the "Stalinist" turn in its aftermath - therein resides
the proper Leninist tragedy. Rosa Luxembourg's famous alternative
"socialism or barbarism" ended up as the ultimate infinite
judgement, asserting the speculative identity of the two opposed terms:
the "really existing" socialism WAS barbarism.27
In the diaries of Georgi Dimitroff, which were recently published
in German,28 we get a unique glimpse into how Stalin was fully aware
what brought him to power, giving an unexpected twist to his well-known
slogan that "people (cadres) are our greatest wealth." When,
at a diner in November 1937, Dimitroff praises the "great luck"
of the international workers, that they had such a genius as their
leader, Stalin, Stalin answers: "... I do not agree with him.
He even expressed himself in a non-Marxist way. /.../ Decisive are
the middle cadres."(7.11.37) He puts it in an even clearer way
a paragraph earlier: "Why did we win over Trotsky and others?
It is well known that, after Lenin, Trotsky was the most popular in
our land. /.../ But we had the support of the middle cadres, and they
explained our grasp of the situation to the masses ... Trotsky did
not pay any attention to these cadres." Here Stalin spells out
the secret of his rise to power: as a rather anonymous General Secretary,
he nominated tens of thousands of cadres who owed their rise to him...
This is why Stalin did not yet want Lenin dead in the early 1922,
rejecting his demand to be given poison to end his life after the
debilitating stroke: if Lenin were to die already in early 1922, the
question of succession would not yet be resolved in Stalin's favor,
since Stalin as the general secretary did not yet penetrate enough
the Party apparatus with his appointees - he needed another year or
two, so that, when Lenin effectively dies, he could count on the support
of thousands of mid-level cadres nominated by him to win over the
big old names of the Bolshevik "aristocracy."
Here are some details of the daily life of Lenin and the Bolsheviks
in 1917 and the following years, which, in their very triviality,
render palpable the gap from the Stalinist nomenklatura. When, in
the evening of 24 October 1917, Lenin left his flat for the Smolny
Institute to coordinate the revolutionary takeover, he took a tram
and asked the conductress if there was any fighting going on in the
center that day. In the years after the October Revolution, Lenin
was mostly driving around in a car only with his faithful driver and
bodyguard Gil; a couple of times they were shot at, stopped by the
police and arrested (the policemen did not recognize Lenin), once,
after visiting a school in suburbs, even robbed of the car and their
guns by bandits posing as police, and then compelled to walk to the
nearest police station. When, on 30 August 1918, Lenin was shot, this
occurred while he got in a conversation with a couple of complaining
women in front of a factory he just visited; the bleeding Lenin was
driven by Gil to Kremlin, were there were no doctors, so his wife
Nadezhda Krupskaya suggested someone should run out to the nearest
grocer's shop for a lemon... The standard meal in the Kremlin kantina
in 1918 was buckwheat porridge and thin vegetable soup. So much about
the privileges of nomenklatura!
Lenin's slanderers like to evoke his famous paranoiac reaction at
listening to Beethoven's appasionata (he first started to cry, then
claimed that a revolutionary cannot afford to let himself go to such
sentiments, because they make him too weak, wanting to pat the enemies
instead of mercilessly fighting them) as the proof of his cold self-control
and cruelty - however, even at its own terms, is this accident effectively
an argument AGAINST Lenin? Does it not rather bear witness to an extreme
sensitivity for music that needs to be kept in check in order to continue
the political struggle? Who of today's cynical politicians still displays
even a trace of such a sensitivity? Is not Lenin here at the very
opposite of the high-ranked Nazis who, without any difficulty, combined
such a sensitivity with the extreme cruelty in taking political decisions
(suffice it to recall Heydrich, the holocaust architect, who, after
a hard day's work, always found time to play with his comrades Beethoven's
string quartets) - is not the proof of Lenin's humanity that, in contrast
to this supreme barbarism, which resides in the very unproblematic
unity of high culture and political barbarism, he was still extremely
sensitive to the irreducible antagonism between art in power struggle?
Furthermore, one is tempted to develop a Leninist theory of this high-cultured
barbarism. Hans Hotter's outstanding 1942 recording of Schubert's
Winterreise seems to call for an intentionally anachronistic reading:
it is easy to imagine German officers and soldiers listening to this
recording in the Stalingrad trenches in the cold Winter of 42/43.
Does the topic of Winterreise not evoke a unique consonance with the
historical moment? Was not the whole campaign to Stalingrad a gigantic
Winterreise, where each German soldier can say for himself the very
first lines of the cycle: "I came here a stranger, / As a stranger
I depart"? Do the following lines not render their basic experience:
"Now the world is so gloomy, / The road shrouded in snow. / I
cannot choose the time / To begin my journey, / Must find my own way
/ In this darkness."
Here we have the endless meaningless march: "It burns under both
my feet, / Even though I walk on ice and snow; / I don't want to catch
my breath / Until I can no longer see the spires." The dream
of returning home in the Spring: "I dreamed of many-colored flowers,
/ The way they bloom in May; / I dreamed of green meadows, / Of merry
bird calls." The nervous waiting for the post: "From the
highroad a posthorn sounds. / Why do you leap so high, my heart?"
The shock of the morning artillery attack: "The cloud tatters
flutter / Around in weary strife. / And fiery red flames / Dart around
among them." Utterly exhausted, the soldiers are refused even
the solace of death: "I'm tired enough to drop, have taken mortal
hurt. / Oh, merciless inn, you turn me away? / Well, onward then,
still further, my loyal walking staff!"
What can one do in such a desperate situation, but to go on with heroic
persistence, closing one's ears to the complaint of the heart, assuming
the heavy burden of fate in a world deserted by Gods? "If the
snow flies in my face, / I shake it off again. / When my heart speaks
in my breast, / I sing loudly and gaily. / I don't hear what it says
to me, / I have no ears to listen; / I don't feel when it laments,
/ Complaining is for fools. / Happy through the world along / Facing
wind and weather! / If there's no God upon the earth, / Then we ourselves
are Gods!"
The obvious counter-argument is that all this is merely a superficial
parallel: even if there is an echo of the atmosphere and emotions,
they are in each case embedded in an entirely different context: in
Schubert, the narrator wanders around in Winter because the beloved
has dropped him, while the German soldiers were on the way to Stalingrad
because of Hitler's military plans. However, it is precisely in this
displacement that the elementary ideological operation consists: the
way for a German soldier to be able to endure his situation was to
avoid the reference to concrete social circumstances which would become
visible through reflection (what the hell were they doing in Russia?
what destruction did they bring to this country? what about killing
the Jews?), and, instead, to indulge in the Romantic bemoaning of
one's miserable fate, as if the large historical catastrophe just
materializes the trauma of a rejected lover. Is this not the supreme
proof of the emotional abstraction, of Hegel's idea that emotions
are ABSTRACT, an escape from the concrete socio-political network
accessible only to THINKING.
And one is tempted to make here a Leninist step further: in our reading
of the Winterreise, we did not just link Schubert to a contingent
later historical catastrophe, we did not just try to imagine how this
song-cycle resonated to the embattled German soldiers in Stalingrad.
What if the link to this catastrophe enables us to read what was wrong
in the Schubertian Romantic position itself? What if the position
of the Romantic tragic hero, narcissistically focused on his own suffering
and despair, elevating them into a source of perverted pleasure, is
already in itself a fake one, an ideological screen masking the true
trauma of the larger historical reality? One should thus accomplish
the properly Hegelian gesture of projecting the split between the
authentic original and its later reading colored by contingent circumstances
back into the authentic original itself: what at first appears the
secondary distortion, a reading twisted by the contingent external
circumstances, tells us something about what the authentic original
itself not only represses, leaves out, but had the function to repress.
Therein resides the Leninist answer to the famous passage from the
Introduction to the Grundrisse manuscript, in which Marx mentions
how easy it is to explain Homer's poetry from its unique historical
context - it is much more difficult to explain its universal appeal,
i.e. why it continues to give us artistic pleasure long after its
historical context disappeared29: this universal appeal is based in
its very ideological function of enabling us to abstract from our
concrete ideologico-political constellation by way of taking refuge
in the "universal" (emotional) content. So, far from signalling
some kind of trans-ideological heritage of the humankind, the universal
attraction of Homer relies on the universalizing gesture of ideology.
"Entre nous: If they kill me..."
In what, then, resides Lenin's greatness? Recall Lenin's shock when,
in the Fall of 1914, the Social Democratic parties adopted the "patriotic
line" - Lenin even thought that the issue of Vorwarts, the daily
newspaper of the German Social Democracy, which reported how Social
Democrats in Reichstag voted for the military credits, was a forgery
of the Russian secret police destined to deceive the Russian workers.
In that era of the military conflict that cut in half the European
continent, how difficult it was to reject the notion that one should
take sides in this conflict, and to fight against the "patriotic
fervor" in one's own country! How many great minds (inclusive
of Freud) succumbed to the nationalist temptation, even if only for
a couple of weeks! This shock of 1914 was - in Badiou's terms - a
desastre, a catastrophe in which an entire world disappeared: not
only the idyllic bourgeois faith in progress, but ALSO the socialist
movement which accompanied it. Lenin himself (the Lenin of What Is
to Be Done?) lost the ground under his feet - there is, in his desperate
reaction, no satisfaction, no "I told you so!" THIS the
moment of Verzweiflung, THIS catastrophe opened up the site for the
Leninist event, for breaking the evolutionary historicism of the Second
International - and only Lenin was the one at the level of this opening,
the one to articulate the Truth of THIS catastrophe.30 Through this
moment of despair, the Lenin who, through reading Hegel, was able
to detect the unique chance for revolution, was born. His State and
Revolution is strictly correlative to this shattering experience -
Lenin's full subjective engagement in it is clear from this famous
letter to Kamenev from July 1917:
"Entre nous: If they kill me, I ask you to publish my notebook
"Marxism & the State" (stuck in Stockholm). It is bound
in a blue cover. It is a collection of all the quotations from Marx
& Engels, likewise from Kautsky against Pannekoek. There is a
series of remarks & notes, formulations. I think with a week's
work it could be published. I consider it imp. for not only Plekhanov
but also Kautsky got it wrong. Condition: all this is entre nous."31
The existential engagement is here extreme, and the kernel of the
Leninist "utopia" arises out of the ashes of the catastrophe
of 1914, in his settling of the accounts with the Second International
orthodoxy: the radical imperative to smash the bourgeois state, which
means the state AS SUCH, and to invent a new communal social form
without a standing army, police or bureaucracy, in which all could
take part in the administration of the social matters. This was for
Lenin no theoretical project for some distant future - in October
1917, Lenin claimed that "we can at once set in motion a state
apparatus constituting of ten if not twenty million people."32
This urge of the moment is the true utopia. One cannot overestimate
the explosive potential of The State and Revolution - in this book,
"the vocabulary and grammar of the Western tradition of politics
was abruptly dispensed with."33 What then followed can be called,
borrowing the title of Althusser's text on Machiavelli, la solitude
de Lenine: the time when he basically stood alone, struggling against
the current in his own party. When, in his "April Theses"
from 1917, Lenin discerned the Augenblick, the unique chance for a
revolution, his proposals were first met with stupor or contempt by
a large majority of his party colleagues. Within the Bolshevik party,
no prominent leader supported his call to revolution, and Pravda took
the extraordinary step of dissociating the party, and the editorial
board as a whole, from Lenin's "April Theses" - far from
being an opportunist flattering and exploiting the prevailing mood
of the populace, Lenin's views were highly idiosyncratic. Bogdanov
characterized "April Theses" as "the delirium of a
madman,"34 and Nadezhda Krupskaya herself concluded that "I
am afraid it looks as if Lenin has gone crazy."35
"Lenin" is not the nostalgic name for old dogmatic certainty;
quite on the contrary, to put it in Kierkegaard's terms, THE Lenin
which we want to retrieve is the Lenin-in-becoming, the Lenin whose
fundamental experience was that of being thrown into a catastrophic
new constellation in which old coordinates proved useless, and who
was thus compelled to REINVENT Marxism - recall his acerb remark apropos
of some new problem: "About this, Marx and Engels said not a
word." The idea is not to return to Lenin, but to REPEAT him
in the Kierkegaardian sense: to retrieve the same impulse in today's
constellation. The return to Lenin aims neither at nostalgically reenacting
the "good old revolutionary times," nor at the opportunistic-pragmatic
adjustment of the old program to "new conditions," but at
repeating, in the present world-wide conditions, the Leninist gesture
of reinventing the revolutionary project in the conditions of imperialism
and colonialism, more precisely: after the politico-ideological collapse
of the long era of progressism in the catastrophe of 1914. Eric Hobsbawn
defined the CONCEPT of the XXth century as the time between 1914,
the end of the long peaceful expansion of capitalism, and 1990, the
emergence of the new form of global capitalism after the collapse
of the Really Existing Socialism. What Lenin did for 1914, we should
do for 1990. "Lenin" stands for the compelling FREEDOM to
suspend the stale existing (post)ideological coordinates, the debilitating
Denkverbot in which we live - it simply means that we are allowed
to think again.
One of the standard accusations against Lenin is that, insensible
for the universal human dimension, he perceived all social events
through the lenses of the class struggle, of "us against them."
However, are Lenin's appeals against the patriotic fervor during the
World War I not an exemplary case of practicing what Alain Badiou36
calls the universal function of "humanity," which has nothing
whatsoever to do with so-called "humanism." This "humanity"
is neither a notional abstraction, nor the pathetic imaginary assertion
of the all-encompassing brotherhood, but a universal function which
actualizes itself in unique ecstatic experiences, like those of the
soldiers from the opposite trenches starting to fraternize. In Jaroslav
Hasek's legendary comical novel The Good Soldier Schwejk, the adventures
of an ordinary Czech soldier who undermines the ruling order by simply
following orders too literally, Schwejk finds himself at the frontline
trenches in Galicia, where the Austrian army is confronting the Russians.
When Austrian soldiers start to shoot, the desperate Schwejk runs
into the no-man's-land in front of their trenches, waving desperately
his hands and shouting: "Don't shoot! There are men on the other
side!" This is what Lenin was aiming at in his call to the tired
peasants and other working masses in the Summer of 1917 to stop fighting,
dismissed as part of a ruthless strategy to win popular support and
thus gain power, even if it meant the military defeat of one's own
country (recall the standard argument that, when, in the Spring of
1917, Lenin was allowed by the German state to pass on a sealed train
through Germany on his way from Switzerland to Sweden, Finland and
then Russia, he was de facto functioning as a German agent).
There is a long literary tradition of elevating the face to face encounter
with an enemy soldier as THE authentic war experience (see the writings
of Ernst Juenger, who celebrated such encounters in his memoirs of
the trench attacks in World War I): soldiers often fantasize about
killing the enemy soldier in a face to face confrontation, looking
him into the eyes before stabbing him. The singular experience of
humanity occurs when the mystique of such a face to face encounter
is rendered meaningless. The same sublime moment of solidarity took
place in the battle for Stalingrad, when, on New Year's Eve of December
31 1942, Russian actors and musicians visited the besieged city to
entertain the troops; the violinist Mikhail Goldstein went to the
trenches to perform a one-man concert for the soldiers:
"The melodies he created drifted out through loudspeakers to
the German trenches and the shooting suddenly ceased. In the eerie
quiet, the music flowed from Goldstein's dipping bow.
When he finished, a hushed silence hung over the Russian soldiers.
From another loudspeaker, in German territory, a voice broke the spell.
In halting Russian it pleaded: 'Play some more Bach. We won't shoot.'
Goldstein picked up his violin and started a lively Bach gavotte."37
This same experience of humanity, of the meaninglessness of the conflict
we are engaged in, can also take a much more mundane shape, that of
a simple exchange of gazes which tells everything. During one of the
anti-apartheid demonstrations in the old South Africa, when a troop
of white policemen was dispersing and pursuing black demonstrators,
a policeman was running after a black lady, a rubber truncheon in
his hand. Unexpectedly, the lady lost one of her shoes; automatically
obeying his "good manners," the policeman picked up the
shoes and gave it to her; at this moment, they exchanged glances and
both became aware of the inanity of their situation - after such a
gesture of politeness, i.e. after handling her the lost shoe and waiting
for her to put it on again, it was simply IMPOSSIBLE for him to continue
to run after her and to hit her with the truncheon; so, after politely
nodding at her, the policeman turned around and walked away... The
moral of this story is NOT that the policeman suddenly discovered
his innate goodness, i.e. we are NOT dealing here with the case of
natural goodness winning over the racist ideological training; on
the contrary, in all probability, the policeman was - as to his psychological
stance - a standard racist. What triumphed here was simply his "superficial"
training in politeness.
When the policeman stretched his hand in order to pass the shoe, this
gesture was more than a moment of physical contact. The white policeman
and the black lady literally lived in two different socio-symbolic
universes with no direct communication possible: for each of the two,
the barrier which separated the two universes was for a brief moment
suspended, and it was as if a hand from another, spectral, universe
reached into one's ordinary reality. The situation is similar to the
scene in one of the early Joan Crawford films (Possessed from 1930),
in which she plays a poor small town girl who, on her way home, has
to stop before the rails since a train is passing slowly through the
small town; through the wagon's windows, she observes the wealthy
life going on inside (a cook preparing an exquisite meal, a couple
dancing...). It is as if she found herself in a cinema theatre, a
spectator confronted with scenes of the life she longs for, scenes
which are close, but nonetheless simultaneously somewhat ethereal,
spectral, threatening to dissolve at any moment. And then, a true
miracle occurs - when the train stops for a brief moment, an elder
kind gentlemen is standing on the observation platform immediately
in front of the girl, with his hand holding a glass with a drink stretching
outwards, from the fantasmatic reality of the train to the everyday
reality of the girl, and engages in a friendly conversation with her
- a magical moments when the dream itself seems to intervene into
our daily reality... The effect of this last shot resides in the way
everyday reality itself - the scene of a train passing by an ordinary
working girl - acquires the magic dimension of the poor girl encountering
her dream. And it is against the background of this scene that one
should interpret the eerie event which took place on the evening of
November 7, 1942, when, in his special train rolling through Thuringia,
Hitler was discussing the day's major news with several aides in the
dining car; since allied air raids had damaged the tracks, the train
frequently slowed its passage:
"While dinner was served on exquisite china, the train stopped
once more at a siding. A few feet away, a hospital train marked time,
and from their tiered cots, wounded soldiers peered into the blazing
light of the dining room where Hitler was immersed in conversation.
Suddenly he looked up at the awed faces staring in at him. In great
anger he ordered the curtains drawn, plunging his wounded warriors
back into the darkness of their own bleak world."38
The miracle of this scene is redoubled: on each side, they experienced
what they saw through the window-frame as a fantasmatic apparition:
for Hitler, it was a nightmarish view of the results of his military
adventure; for the soldiers, it was the unexpected encounter with
the Leader himself. The true miracle would have been here if a hand
were to stretch through the window - say, Hitler reaching over to
a wounded soldier. But, of course, it was precisely such an encounter,
such an intrusion into his reality, that Hitler dreaded, so, instead
of stretching his hand, he in panic ordered the curtains drawn.
A Cyberspace Lenin?
So what are we to say to the standard reproach of "extremism"?
Lenin's critique of the "Leftism as the Child Illness of the
Communism" is more than actual in the last decades, in which
Left often succumbed to the terrorist temptation. Political "extremism"
or "excessive radicalism" should always be read as a phenomenon
of ideologico-political displacement: as an index of its opposite,
of a limitation, of a refusal effectively to "go to the end."
What was the Jacobin's recourse to radical "terror" if not
a kind of hysterical acting out bearing witness to their inability
to disturb the very fundamentals of economic order (private property,
etc.)? And does the same not go even for the so-called "excesses"
of Political Correctness? Do they also not display the retreat from
disturbing the effective (economic etc.) causes of racism and sexism?
Perhaps, then, the time has come to render problematic the standard
topos, shared by practically all the "postmodern" Leftists,
according to which political "totalitarianism" somehow results
from the predominance of material production and technology over the
intersubjective communication and/or symbolic practice, as if the
root of the political terror resides in the fact that the "principle"
of instrumental reason, of the technological exploitation of nature,
is extended also to society, so that people are treated as raw stuff
to be transformed into a New Man. What if it is the exact opposite
which holds? What if political "terror" signals precisely
that the sphere of (material) production is denied in its autonomy
and subordinated to political logic? Is it not that all political
"terror," from Jacobins to Maoist Cultural Revolution, presupposes
the foreclosure of production proper, its reduction to the terrain
of political battle?
Recall Badiou's exalted defense of Terror in the French Revolution,
in which he quotes the justification of the guillotine for Lavoisier:
"La republique n'a pas de besoin de savants. /The Republic has
no need for scientists./" Badiou's thesis is that the truth of
this statement emerges if we cut it short, depriving it of its caveat:
"La republique n'a pas de besoins. /The Republic has no needs./"
The Republic gives body to the purely political logic of equality
and freedom which should follow its path with no consideration for
the "servicing of goods" destined to satisfy the needs of
the individuals.39 In the revolutionary process proper, freedom becomes
an end-in-itself, caught in its own paroxysm - this suspension of
the importance of the sphere of economy, of the (material) production,
brings Badiou close to Hannah Arendt for whom, in a strict homology
to Badiou, freedom is opposed to the domain of the provision of services
and goods, of the maintenance of households and the exercise of administration,
which do not belong to politics proper: the only place for freedom
is the communal political space. In this precise sense, Badiou's (and
Sylvain Lazarus'40) plea for the reappraisal of Lenin is more ambiguous
than it may appear: what it effectively amounts to is nothing less
than the abandonment of Marx's key insight into how the political
struggle is a spectacle which, in order to be deciphered, has to be
referred to the sphere of economics ("if Marxism had any analytical
value for political theory, was it not in the insistence that the
problem of freedom was contained in the social relations implicitly
declared 'unpolitical' - that is, naturalized - in liberal discourse"41).
No wonder that the Lenin Badiou and Lazarus prefer is the Lenin of
What Is to Be Done?, the Lenin who (in his thesis that the socialist-revolutionary
consciousness has to be brought from without to the working class)
breaks with Marx's alleged "economism" and asserts the autonomy
of the Political, NOT the Lenin of The State and Revolution, fascinated
by the modern centralized industry, imagining the (depoliticized)
ways to reorganize economy and the state apparatus.
What all the new French (or French oriented) theories of the Political,
from Balibar through Ranciere and Badiou to Laclau and Mouffe, aim
at is - to put it in the traditional philosophical terms - the reduction
of the sphere of economy (of the material production) to an "ontic"
sphere deprived of the "ontological" dignity. Within this
horizon, there is simply no place for the Marxian "critique of
political economy": the structure of the universe of commodities
and capital in Marx's Capital is NOT just that of a limited empirical
sphere, but a kind of socio-transcendental a priori, the matrix which
generates the totality of social and political relations. The relationship
between economy and politics is ultimately that of the well-known
visual paradox of the "two faces or a vase": one either
sees the two faces or a vase, never both of them - one has to make
a choice.42 In the same way, one either focuses on the political,
and the domain of economy is reduced to the empirical "servicing
of goods," or one focuses on economy, and politics is reduced
to a theater of appearances, to a passing phenomenon which will disappear
with the arrival of the developed Communist (or technocratic) society,
in which, as already Engels put it, the "administration of people"
will vanish in the "administration of things."43
The root of this notion of pure "politics," radically autonomous
with regard to history, society, economy, State, even Party, is Badiou's
opposition between Being and Event - it is here that Badiou remains
"idealist." From the materialist standpoint, an Event emerges
"out of nowhere" within a specific constellation of Being
- the space of an Event is the minimal "empty" distance
between two beings, the "other" dimension which shines through
this gap.44 So when Badiou and Lazarus insist on the strict frontier
between the Political and the Social (the domain of State, historicism...),
they concede too much - namely, that SOCIETY EXISTS. They do not get
the lesson, articulated by Laclau, that "society doesn't exist,"
that society is not a positive field, since the gap of the Political
is inscribed into its very foundations (Marx's name for the political
which traverses the entire social body is "class struggle").
Consequently, Lenin the ultimate political strategist should in no
way be separated from Lenin the "technocrat" dreaming about
the scientific reorganization of production. The greatness of Lenin
is that, although he lacked the proper conceptual apparatus to think
these two levels together, he was aware of the urgency to do it -
an impossible, yet necessary, task.45 What we are dealing with here
is another version of the Lacanian "il n'y a pas de rapport...":
if, for Lacan, there is no sexual relationship, then, for Marxism
proper, there is no relationship between economy and politics, no
"meta-language" enabling us to grasp from the same neutral
standpoint the two levels, although - or, rather, BECAUSE - these
two levels are inextricably intertwined. The "political"
class struggle takes place in the very midst of economy (recall that
the very last paragraph of Capital III, where the texts abruptly stops,
tackles the class struggle), while, at the same time, the domain of
economy serves as the key enabling us to decode political struggles.
No wonder that the structure of this impossible relationship is that
of the Moebius band: first, we have to progress from the political
spectacle to its economic infrastructure; then, in the second step,
we have to confront the irreducible dimension of the political struggle
in the very heart of the economy.
Here, Lenin's stance against economism as well as against pure politics
is crucial today, apropos of the split attitude towards economy in
(what remains of) the radical circles: on the one hand, the above-mentioned
pure "politicians" who abandon economy as the site of struggle
and intervention; on the other hand, the economists, fascinated by
the functioning of today's global economy, who preclude any possibility
of a political intervention proper. Today, more than ever, we should
here return to Lenin: yes, economy is the key domain, the battle will
be decided there, one has to break the spell of the global capitalism
- BUT the intervention should be properly POLITICAL, not economic.
The battle to be fought is thus a twofold one: first, yes, anticapitalism.
However, anticapitalism without problematizing the capitalism's POLITICAL
form (liberal parliamentary democracy) is not sufficient, no matter
how "radical" it is. Perhaps THE lure today is the belief
that one can undermine capitalism without effectively problematizing
the liberal-democratic legacy which - as some Leftists claim - although
engendered by capitalism, acquired autonomy and can serve to criticize
capitalism. This lure is strictly correlative to its apparent opposite,
to the pseudo-Deleuzian love-hate fascinating/fascinated poetic depiction
of Capital as a rhizomatic monstre/vampire which deterritorializes
and swallows all, indomitable, dynamic, ever raising from the dead,
each crisis making it stronger, Dionysos-Phoenix reborn... It is in
this poetic (anti)capitalist reference to Marx that Marx is really
dead: appropriated when deprived of his political sting.
Marx was fascinated by the revolutionary "deterritorializing"
impact of capitalism which, in its inexorable dynamics, undermines
all stable traditional forms of human interaction; what hey approached
capitalism with is that its "deterritorialization" was not
thorough enough, that it generated new "reterritorializations"
- the ultimate obstacle to capitalism is capitalism itself, i.e. capitalism
unleashes a dynamics it is no longer be able to contain. Far from
being outdated, this claim seems to gain actuality with today's growing
deadlocks of globalization in which the inherently antagonistic nature
of capitalism belies its worldwide triumph. However, the problem is:
is it still possible to imagine Communism (or another form of post-capitalist
society) as a formation which sets free the deterritorializing dynamics
of capitalism, liberating it of its inherent constraints? Marx's fundamental
vision was that a new, higher social order (Communism) is possible,
an order that would not only maintain, but even raise to a higher
degree and effectively fully release the potential of the self-increasing
spiral of productivity which, in capitalism, on account of its inherent
obstacle/contradiction, is again and again thwarted by socially destructive
economic crises. What Marx overlooked is that, to put it in the standard
Derridean terms, this inherent obstacle/antagonism as the "condition
of impossibility" of the full deployment of the productive forces
is simultaneously its "condition of possibility": if we
abolish the obstacle, the inherent contradiction of capitalism, we
do not get the fully unleashed drive to productivity finally delivered
of its impediment, but we lose precisely this productivity that seemed
to be generated and simultaneously thwarted by capitalism - if we
take away the obstacle, the very potential thwarted by this obstacle
dissipates... therein would reside a possible Lacanian critique of
Marx, focusing on the ambiguous overlapping between surplus-value
and surplus-enjoyment.46
While this constant self-propelling revolutionizing still holds for
the high Stalinism with its total productive mobilization, the "stagnant"
late Real Socialism legitimizes itself (between the lines, at least)
as a society in which one can live peacefully, avoiding the capitalist
competitive stress. This was the last line of defense when, from the
late 60s onwards, after the fall of Khrustchow (the last enthusiast
who, during his visit to the US, prophesied that "your grandchildren
will be Communists"), it became clear that the Real Socialism
was losing the competitive edge in its war with capitalism. So the
stagnant late Real Socialism in a way already WAS "socialism
with a human face": silently abandoning great historical tasks,
it provided the security of the everyday life going on in a benevolent
boredom. Today's Ostalgie for the defunct Socialism mostly consists
in such a conservative nostalgia for the self-satisfied constrained
way of life; even the nostalgic anti-capitalist artists from Peter
Handke to Joseph Beuys celebrate this aspect of Socialism: the absence
of stressful mobilization and frantic commodification. Of course,
this unexpected shift tells us something about the deficiency of the
original Marxist project itself: it points towards the limitation
of its goal of unleashed productive mobilization.
Capitalism is not just a historical epoch among others - in a way,
the once fashionable and today forgotten Francis Fukuyama WAS right,
global capitalism IS "the end of history." A certain excess
which was as it were kept under check in previous history, perceived
as a localizable perversion, as an excess, a deviation, is in capitalism
elevated into the very principle of social life, in the speculative
movement of money begetting more money, of a system which can survive
only by constantly revolutionizing its own conditions, that is to
say, in which the thing can only survive as its own excess, constantly
exceeding its own "normal" constraints. Let us take the
case of consumption: before modernity, we were dealing with the direct
opposition between moderate consumption and its excess (gluttony,
etc.); with capitalism, the excess (the consumption of "useless
things") becomes THE RULE, i.e. the elementary form of buying
is the act of buying things we "do NOT really need." And,
perhaps, it is only today, in the global capitalism in its "postindustrial"
digitalized form, that, to put it in Hegelian terms, the really-existing
capitalism is reaching the level of its notion: perhaps, one should
follow again Marx's old anti-evolutionist motto (incidentally, taken
verbatim from Hegel) that the anatomy of man provides the key for
the anatomy of a monkey, i.e. that, in order to deploy the inherent
notional structure of a social formation, one must start with its
most developed form. Marx located the elementary capitalist antagonism
in the opposition between use- and exchange-value: in capitalism,
the potentials of this opposition are fully realized, the domain of
exchange-values is acquires autonomy, is transformed into the specter
of self-propelling speculative capital which needs the productive
capacities and needs of actual people only as its dispensable temporal
embodiment. Marx derived the very notion of economic crisis from this
gap: a crisis occurs when reality catches up with the illusory self-generating
mirage of money begetting more money - this speculative madness cannot
go on indefinitely, it has to explode in ever stronger crises. The
ultimate root of the crisis is for him the gap between use and exchange
value: the logic of exchange value follows its own path, its own mad
dance, irrespective of the real needs of real people. It may appear
that this analysis is more than actual today, when the tension between
the virtual universe and the real is reaching almost palpably unbearable
proportions: on the one hand, we have crazy solipsistic speculations
about futures, mergers, etc., following their own inherent logic;
on the other hand, reality is catching up in the guise of ecological
catastrophes, poverty, the Third World collapse of social life, the
Mad Cow Disease. This is why cyber-capitalists can appear as the paradigmatic
capitalists today, this is why Bill Gates can dream of the cyberspace
as providing the frame for what he calls "frictionless capitalism."
What we have here is an ideological short-circuit between the two
version of the gap between reality and virtuality: the gap between
real production and virtual spectral domain of the Capital, and the
gap between experiential reality and virtual reality of cyberspace.
It effectively seems that the cyberspace gap between my fascinating
screen persona and the miserable flesh which is "me" off
the screen translates into the immediate experience the gap between
the Real of the speculative circulation of the capital and the drab
reality of impoverished masses... However, is this - this recourse
to "reality" which will sooner or later catch up with the
virtual game - really the only way to operationalize a critique of
capitalism? What if the problem of capitalism is not this solipsistic
mad dance, but precisely the opposite: that it continues to disavow
its gap with "reality," that it presents itself as serving
real needs of real people? The originality of Marx is that he played
on both cards simultaneously: the origin of capitalist crises is the
gap between use- and exchange-value, AND capitalism constrains the
free deployment of productivity.
What all this means is that the urgent task of the economic analysis
today is, again, to REPEAT Marx's "critique of political economy,
without succumbing to the temptation of the multitude of the ideologies
of "postindustrial" societies. The key change concerns the
status of private property: the ultimate element of power and control
is no longer the last link in the chain of investments, the firm or
individual who "really owns" the means of production. The
ideal capitalist today functions in a wholly different way: investing
borrowed money, "really owning" nothing, even indebted,
but nonetheless controlling things. A corporation is owned by another
corporation, which is again borrowing money from banks, which may
ultimately manipulate money owned by ordinary people like ourselves.
With Bill Gates, the "private property of the means of production"
becomes meaningless, at least in the standard meaning of the term.
The paradox of this virtualization of capitalism is ultimately the
same as that of the electron in the elementary particle physics. The
mass of each element in our reality is composed of its mass at rest
plus the surplus provided by the acceleration of its movement; however,
an electron's mass at rest is zero, its mass consists only of the
surplus generated by the acceleration of its movement, as if we are
dealing with a nothing which acquires some deceptive substance only
by magically spinning itself into an excess of itself. Does today's
virtual capitalist not function in a homologous way - his "net
value" is zero, he directly operates just with the surplus, borrowing
from the future?47
So where is Lenin in all this? According to the predominant doxa,
in the years after the October Revolution, Lenin's decline of the
faith in the creative capacities of the masses led him to emphasize
the role of science and the scientists, to rely on the authority of
the expert: he hailed "the beginning of that very happy time
when politics will recede into the background, /.../ and engineers
and agronomists will do most of the talking."48 Technocratic
post-politics? Lenin's ideas about how the road to socialism runs
through the terrain of monopoly capitalism may appear dangerously
naive today:
"Capitalism has created an accounting apparatus in the shape
of the banks, syndicates, postal service, consumers' societies, and
office employees unions. Without big banks socialism would be impossible.
/.../ our task is here merely to lop off what capitalistically mutilates
this excellent apparatus, to make it even bigger, even more democratic,
even more comprehensive. /.../ This will be country-wide book-keeping,
country-wide accounting of the production and distribution of goods,
this will be, so to speak, something in the nature of the skeleton
of socialist society."49
Is this not the most radical expression of Marx's notion of the general
intellect regulating all social life in a transparent way, of the
postpolitical world in which "administration of people"
is supplanted by the "administration of things"? It is,
of course, easy to play against this quote the tune of the "critique
on instrumental reason" and "administered world /verwaltete
Welt/": the "totalitarian" potentials are inscribed
in this very form of total social control. It is easy to remark sarcastically
how, in the Stalinist epoch, the apparatus of social administration
effectively became "even bigger." Furthermore, is this postpolitical
vision not the very opposite of the Maoist notion of the eternity
of the class struggle ("everything is political")?
Are, however, things really so unambiguous? What if one replaces the
(obviously dated) example of the central bank with the World Wide
Web, today's perfect candidate for the General Intellect? Dorothy
Sayers claimed that Aristoteles' Poetics effectively is the theory
of the detective novels avant la lettre - since the poor Aristotle
didn't yet know of the detective novel, he had to refer to the only
examples at his disposal, the tragedies... Along the same lines, Lenin
was effectively developing the theory of a role of World Wide Web,
but, since WWW was unknown to him, he had to refer to the unfortunate
central banks. Consequently, can one also say that "without the
World Wide Web socialism would be impossible. /.../ our task is here
merely to lop off what capitalistically mutilates this excellent apparatus,
to make it even bigger, even more democratic, even more comprehensive"?
In these conditions, one is tempted to resuscitate the old, opprobrious
and half-forgotten, Marxian dialectics of the productive forces and
the relations of production: it is already a commonplace to claim
that, ironically, it was this very dialectics which buried the Really
Existing Socialism: Socialism was not able to sustain the passage
from industrial to postindustrial economy. However, does capitalism
really provide the "natural" frame of the relations of production
for the digital universe? Is there not in the World Wide Web an explosive
potential also for capitalism itself? Is not the lesson of the Microsoft
monopoly precisely the Leninist one: instead of fighting its monopoly
through the state apparatus (recall the court-ordered split of the
Microsoft Corporation), would it not be more "logical" just
to SOCIALIZE it, rendering it freely accessible?50
So what about the basic reproach according to which, Lenin is irrelevant
for us today because he remained stuck within the horizon of the industrial
mass production (recall his celebration of Fordism)? The first thing
to do here is to ask the elementary question: what is a factory? Leslie
Kaplan's essay-poem L'exces-usine,51 with its description of the "Hell"
of the factory life, renders palpable the dimension overlooked in
the standard Marxist depictions of the workers' "alienation."
Kaplan opposes the self-enclosed universe of the factory to the open
environment of the previous work-process: the factory space is a timeless
space in which fiction and reality ultimately coincide, i.e. the very
reality of this space functions as the fantasmatic space cut off from
its environs. What is lacking in this space is the full "background
noise" which provides the life-world context to human individuals:
in a factory, as Kaplan puts it, instead of the rich tapestry of the
background-environment, there is only a whiteness - in short, it is
as if, when we are in a factory, we enter an artificial universe which
is deprived of the substantial wealth of the real-life texture. In
this space, (historical-narrative) memory itself is threatened: workers
are cut off their ancestral roots, and this also affects their utopian
potentials themselves: reduced to robots endlessly repeating the same
mechanical gestures, they lose the very capacity to dream, to devise
projects of alternate reality. What they experience is no longer the
nostalgia for a determinate past (say, of their previous more "organic"
farmers' lives), but, as Kaplan puts it perspicuously, the "absolute
nostalgia" for an empty Otherness whose sole positive content
is, again, the factory life itself - say, the empty corridors of a
factory.
So, within these coordinates, what does the passage from the factory
production to the "postindustrial" production in which workers
are again isolated and can even work at home, behind their computer
screen, mean? The disabling alternative of today's Marxism is: what
to do apropos of the growing importance of the "immaterial production"
today (cyber-workers)? Do we insist that only those involved in "real"
material production are the working class, or do we accomplish the
fateful step of accepting that the "symbolic workers" are
the (true) proletarians today? One should resist this step, because
it obfuscates the DIVISION between immaterial and material production,
the SPLIT in the working class between (as a rule geographically separated)
cyber-workers and material workers (programmers in the US or India,
the sweat shops in China or Indonesia). Perhaps, it is the figure
of the UNEMPLOYED (JOBLESS) who stands for the pure proletarian today:
the unemployed substantial determination remains that of a worker,
but they are prevented from actualizing it OR to renounce it, so they
remain suspended in the potentiality of workers who cannot work. Perhaps,
we are today in a sense "all jobless": jobs tend to be more
and more based on short term contracts, so that the jobless state
is the rule, the zero-level, and the temporary job the exception.
The key antagonism of the so-called new (digital) industries is thus:
how to maintain the form of (private) property, within which only
the logic of profit can be maintained (see also the Napster problem,
the free circulation of music). And do the legal complications in
biogenetics not point in the same direction? The key element of the
new international trade agreements is the "protection of intellectual
property": whenever, in a merger, a big First World company takes
over a Third World company, the first thing they do is close down
the research department. Phenomena emerge here which bring the notion
of property to extraordinary dialectical paradoxes: in India, the
local communities suddenly discover that medical practices and materials
they are using for centuries are now owned by American companies,
so they should be bought from them; with the biogenetic companies
patentizing genes, we are all discovering that parts of ourselves,
our genetic components, are already copyrighted, owned by others...
However, the outcome of this crisis of the private property of the
means of production is by no means guaranteed - it is HERE that one
should take into account the ultimate paradox of the Stalinist society:
against the capitalism which is the class society, but in principle
egalitarian, without direct hierarchical divisions, the "mature"
Stalinism is a classless society articulated in precisely defined
hierarchical groups (top nomenklatura, technical intelligence, army...).
What this means is that, already for Stalinism, the classic Marxist
notion of the class struggle is no longer adequate to describe its
hierarchy and domination: in the Soviet Union from the late 20s onwards,
the key social division was not defined by property, but by the direct
access to power mechanisms and to the privileged material and cultural
conditions of life (food, accommodation, healthcare, freedom of travel,
education). And, perhaps, the ultimate irony of history will be that,
in the same way Lenin's vision of the "central bank Socialism"
can be properly read only retroactively, from today's World Wide Web,
the Soviet Union provided the first model of the developed "post-property"
society, of the true "late capitalism" in which the ruling
class will be defined by the direct access to the (informational,
administrative) means of social power and control and to other material
and social privileges: the point will no longer be to own companies,
but directly to run them, to have the right to use a private jet,
to have access to top health care, etc. - privileges which will be
acquired not by property, but by other (educational, managerial, etc.)
mechanisms.
Today, we already can discern the signs of a kind of general unease
- recall the series of events usually listed under the name of "Seattle."
The 10 years honeymoon of the triumphant global capitalism is over,
the long-overdue "seven years itch" is here - witness the
panicky reactions of the big media, which - from the Time magazine
to CNN - all of a sudden started to warn about the Marxists manipulating
the crowd of the "honest" protesters. The problem is now
the strictly Leninist one - how to ACTUALIZE the media's accusations:
how to invent the organizational structure which will confer on this
unrest the FORM of the universal political demand. Otherwise, the
momentum will be lost, and what will remain is the marginal disturbance,
perhaps organized as a new Greenpeace, with certain efficiency, but
also strictly limited goals, marketing strategy, etc. In other words,
the key "Leninist" lesson today is: politics without the
organizational FORM of the party is politics without politics, so
the answer to those who want just the (quite adequately named) "New
SOCIAL Movements" is the same as the answer of the Jacobins to
the Girondin compromisers: "You want revolution without a revolution!"
Today's blockade is that there are two ways open for the socio-political
engagement: either play the game of the system, engage in the "long
march through the institutions," or get active in new social
movements, from feminism through ecology to anti-racism. And, again,
the limit of these movements is that they are not POLITICAL in the
sense of the Universal Singular: they are "one issue movements"
which lack the dimension of the universality, i.e. they do not relate
to the social TOTALITY.
Here, Lenin's reproach to liberals is crucial: they only EXPLOIT the
working classes' discontent to strengthen their position vis-a-vis
the conservatives, instead of identifying with it to the end.52 Is
this also not the case with today's Left liberals? They like to evoke
racism, ecology, workers' grievances, etc., to score points over the
conservatives WITHOUT ENDANGERING THE SYSTEM. Recall how, in Seattle,
Bill Clinton himself deftly referred to the protesters on the streets
outside, reminding the gathered leaders inside the guarded palaces
that they should listen to the message of the demonstrators (the message
which, of course, Clinton interpreted, depriving it of its subversive
sting attributed to the dangerous extremists introducing chaos and
violence into the majority of peaceful protesters). It's the same
with all New Social Movements, up to the Zapatistas in Chiapas: the
systemic politics is always ready to "listen to their demands,"
depriving them of their proper political sting. The system is by definition
ecumenical, open, tolerant, ready to "listen" to all - even
if one insist on one's demands, they are deprived of their universal
political sting by the very form of negotiation. The true Third Way
we have to look for is this third way between the institutionalized
parliamentary politics and the new social movements.
The ultimate answer to the reproach that the radical Left proposals
are utopian should thus be that, today, the true utopia is the belief
that the present liberal-democratic capitalist consensus could go
on indefinitely, without radical changes. We are thus back at the
old '68 motto "Soyons realistes, demandons l'impossible!":
in order to be truly a "realist," one must consider breaking
out of the constraints of what appears "possible" (or, as
we usually out it, "feasible").
The Leninist Utopia
Which, then, is the criterion of the political act? Success as such
clearly doesn't count, even if we define it in the dialectical way
of Merleau-Ponty, as the wager that future will retroactively redeem
our present horrible acts (this is how, in his Humanism and Terror,
Merleau-Ponty provided one of the more intelligent justifications
of the Stalinist terror: retroactively, it will become justified if
its final outcome will be true freedom)53; neither does the reference
to some abstract-universal ethical norms. The only criteria is the
absolutely INHERENT one: that of the ENACTED UTOPIA. In a proper revolutionary
breakthrough, the utopian future is neither simply fully realized,
present, nor simply evoked as a distant promise which justified present
violence - it is rather as if, in a unique suspension of temporality,
in the short-circuit between the present and the future, we are -
as if by Grace - for a brief time allowed to act AS IF the utopian
future is (not yet fully here, but) already at hand, just there to
be grabbed. Revolution is not experienced as a present hardship we
have to endure for the happiness and freedom of the future generations,
but as the present hardship over which this future happiness and freedom
already cast their shadow - in it, we ALREADY ARE FREE WHILE FIGHTING
FOR FREEDOM, we ALREADY ARE HAPPY WHILE FIGHTING FOR HAPPINESS, no
matter how difficult the circumstances. Revolution is not a Merlo-Pontyan
wager, an act suspended in the futur anterieur, to be legitimized
or delegitimized by the long term outcome of the present acts; it
is as it were ITS OWN ONTOLOGICAL PROOF, an immediate index of its
own truth.
Let us recall the staged performance of "Storming the Winter
Palace" in Petrograd, on the third anniversary of the October
Revolution, on 7 November 1920. Tens of thousands of workers, soldiers,
students and artists worked round the clock, living on kasha (the
tasteless wheat porridge), tea and frozen apples, and preparing the
performance at the very place where the event "really took place"
three years earlier; their work was coordinated by the Army officers,
as well as by the avant-garde artists, musicians and directors, from
Malevich to Meyerhold. Although this was acting and not "reality,"
the soldiers and sailors were playing themselves - many of them not
only actually participated in the event of 1917, but were also simultaneously
involved in the real battles of the Civil War that were raging in
the near vicinity of Petrograd, a city under siege and suffering from
severe shortages of food. A contemporary commented on the performance:
"The future historian will record how, throughout one of the
bloodiest and most brutal revolutions, all of Russia was acting"54;
and the formalist theoretician Viktor Shklovski noted that "some
kind of elemental process is taking place where the living fabric
of life is being transformed into the theatrical."55 We all remember
the infamous self-celebratory First of May parades that were one of
the supreme signs of recognition of the Stalinist regimes - if one
needs a proof of how Leninism functioned in an entirely different
way, are such performances not the supreme proof that the October
Revolution was definitely NOT a simple coup d'etat by the small group
of Bolsheviks, but an event which unleashed a tremendous emancipatory
potential?
The archetypal Eisensteinian cinematic scene rendering the exuberant
orgy of revolutionary destructive violence (what Eisenstein himself
called "a veritable bacchanalia of destruction") belongs
to the same series: when, in October, the victorious revolutionaries
penetrate the wine cellars of the Winter Palace, they indulge there
in the ecstatic orgy of smashing thousands of the expensive wine bottles;
in Behzin Meadow, after the village Pioneers discovers the body of
the young Pavlik, brutally murdered by his own father, they force
their way into the local church and desecrate it, robbing it of its
relics, squabbling over an icon, sacrilegiously trying on vestments,
heretically laughing at the statuary... In this suspension of the
goal-oriented instrumental activity, we effectively get a kind of
Bataillean "unrestrained expenditure" - the pious desire
to deprive the revolution of this excess is simply the desire to have
a revolution without revolution. It is against this background that
one should approach the delicate issue of revolutionary violence which
is an authentic act of liberation, not just a blind passage a l'acte.56
And did we not get exactly the same scene in the Great Cultural Revolution
in China, with the thousands of Red Guardists ecstatically destroying
old historical monuments, smashing old vases, desecrating old paintings,
chirping off old walls?57 In spite of (or, rather, because of) all
its horrors, the Great Cultural Revolution undoubtedly did contain
elements of such an enacted utopia. At its very end, before the agitation
was blocked by Mao himself (since he already achieved his goal of
reestablishing his full power and getting rid of the top nomenklatura
competition), there was the "Shanghai Commune": one million
workers who simply took the official slogans seriously, demanding
the abolition of the State and even the Party itself, and the direct
communal organization of society. It is significant that it was at
this very point that Mao ordered the restoration of order. The (often
noted) parallel between Mao and Lacan is fully justified here: the
dissolution of the Ecole Freudienne de Paris in 1979 was Lacan's "Great
Cultural Revolution," mobilizing his young followers (who, incidentally,
mostly were ex-Maoists from 1968!) in order to get rid of the inner
circle of his "mandarins." In both cases, the paradox is
that of a leader who triggers an uncontrolled upheaval, while trying
to exert full personal power - the paradoxical overlapping of extreme
dictatorship and extreme emancipation of the masses.
It is at this precise point concerning political terror that one can
locate the gap that separates Leninism from Stalinism58: in Lenin's
times, terror was openly admitted (Trotsky sometimes even boasted
in an almost cocky way about the non-democratic nature of the Bolshevik
regime and the terror it used), while in Stalin's times, the symbolic
status of the terror thoroughly changed: terror turned into the publicly
non-acknowledged obscene shadowy supplement of the public official
discourse. It is significant that the climax of terror (1936/37) took
place after the new constitution was accepted in 1935 - this constitution
was supposed to end the state of emergency and to mark the return
of the things to normal: the suspension of the civil rights of the
whole strata of population (kulaks, ex-capitalists) was recalled,
the right to vote was now universal, etc.etc. The key idea of this
constitution was that now, after the stabilization of the Socialist
order and the annihilation of the enemy classes, the Soviet Union
is no longer a class society: the subject of the State is no longer
the working class (workers and peasants), but the people. However,
this does NOT mean that the Stalinist constitution was a simple hypocrisy
concealing the social reality - the possibility of terror is inscribed
into its very core: since the class war is now proclaimed over and
the Soviet Union is conceived of as the classless country of the People,
those who (are still presumed to) oppose the regime are no longer
mere class enemies in a conflict that tears apart the social body,
but enemies of the People, insects, worthless scum, which is to be
excluded from humanity itself.
This repression of the regime's own excess was strictly correlative
to something homologous to the invention of the liberal psychological
individual not take place in the Soviet Union in the late 20s and
early 30s. The Russian avant-garde art of the early 20s (futurism,
constructivism) not only zealously endorsed industrialization, it
even endeavored to reinvent a new industrial man - no longer the old
man of sentimental passions and roots in traditions, but the new man
who gladly accepts his role as a bolt or screw in the gigantic coordinated
industrial Machine. As such, it was subversive in its very "ultra-orthodoxy,"
i.e. in its over-identification with the core of the official ideology:
the image of man that we get in Eisenstein, Meyerhold, constructivist
paintings, etc., emphasizes the beauty of his/her mechanical movements,
his/her thorough depsychologization. What was perceived in the West
as the ultimate nightmare of liberal individualism, as the ideological
counterpoint to the "Taylorization," to the Fordist ribbon-work,
was in Russia hailed as the utopian prospect of liberation: recall
how Meyerhold violently asserted the "behaviorist" approach
to acting - no longer emphatic familiarization with the person the
actor is playing, but the ruthless bodily training aimed at the cold
bodily discipline, at the ability of the actor to perform the series
of mechanized movements...59 THIS is what was unbearable to AND IN
the official Stalinist ideology, so that the Stalinist "socialist
realism" effectively WAS an attempt to reassert a "Socialism
with a human face," i.e. to reinscribe the process of industrialization
into the constraints of the traditional psychological individual:
in the Socialist Realist texts, paintings and films, individuals are
no longer rendered as parts of the global Machine, but as warm passionate
persons.
In a recent pamphlet against the "excesses" of May '68 and,
more generally, the "sexual liberation" of the 60s, The
Independent brought back to memory what the radicals of the '68 thought
about the child sex. A quarter of a century ago, Daniel Cohn-Bendit
wrote about his experience in a kindergarten: "My constant flirt
with all the children soon took on erotic characteristics. I could
really feel how from the age of five the small girls had already learned
to make passes at me. /.../ Several times a few children opened the
flies of my trousers and started to stroke me. /.../ When they insisted,
I then stroked them." Shulamith Firestone went even further,
expressing her hopes that, in a world "without the incest taboo
/.../ relations with children would include as much genital sex as
they were capable of - probably considerably more than we now believe."60
When confronted with these statements, Cohn-Bendit played them down,
claiming that "this did not really happen, I only wanted to provoke
people. When one reads it today, it is unacceptable."61 However,
the question still hovers: how, at that time, was it possible to provoke
people, presenting them sexual games with pre-school children as something
appealing, while today, the same "provocation" would immediately
give rise to an outburst of moral disgust? After all, child sexual
harassment is one of THE notions of Evil today. Without directly taking
sides in this debate, one should read it as a sign of the change in
our mores from the utopian energies of the 60s and early 70s to the
contemporary stale Political Correctness, in which every authentic
encounter with another human being is denounced as a victimizing experience.
What we are unable even to conjecture today is the idea of REVOLUTION,
be it sexual or social. Perhaps, in today's stale times of the proliferating
pleas for tolerance, one should take the risk of recalling the liberating
dimension of such "excesses."
Perhaps the most succinct definition of ideology was produced by Christopher
Hitchens, when he tackled the difficult question of what the North
Koreans effectively think about their "Beloved Leader" Kim
Yong Il: "mass delusion is the only thing that keeps a people
sane."62 This paradox points towards the fetishistic split in
the very heart of an effectively functioning ideology: individuals
transpose their belief onto the big Other (embodied in the collective),
which thus believes in their place - individuals thus remain sane
qua individuals, maintaining the distance towards the "big Other"
of the official discourse. It is not only the direct identification
with the ideological "delusion" which would render individuals
insane, but also the suspension of their (disavowed, displaced) belief.
In other words, if individuals were to be deprived of this belief
(projected onto the "big Other"), they would have to jump
in and themselves directly assume the belief. (Perhaps, this explains
the paradox that many a cynic turns into a sincere believer at the
very point of the disintegration of the "official" belief.)
This is what Lacan aimed at in his claim that the true formula of
materialism is not "God doesn't exist," but "God is
unconscious" - suffice it to recall what, in a letter to Max
Brod, Milena Jesenska wrote about Kafka: "Above all, things like
money, stock-exchange, the foreign currency administration, type-writer,
are for him thoroughly mystical (what they effectively are, only not
for us, the others)."63One should read this statement against
the background of Marx's analysis of commodity fetishism: the fetishist
illusion resides in our real social life, not in our perception of
it - a bourgeois subject knows very well that there is nothing magic
about money, that money is just an object which stands for a set of
social relations, but he nevertheless ACTS in real life as if he were
to believe that money is a magic thing. This, then, gives us a precise
insight into Kafka's universe: Kafka was able to experience directly
these fantasmatic beliefs we, "normal" people, disavow -
Kafka's "magic" is what Marx liked to refer to as the "theological
freakishness" of commodities.
This definition of ideology points out the way to answer the boring
standard reproach against the application of psychoanalysis to social-ideological
processes: is it "legitimate" to expand the use of the notions
which were originally deployed for the treatment of individuals, to
collective entities and to speak, say, of religion as a "collective
compulsive neurosis"? The focus of psychoanalysis is entirely
different: the Social, the field of social practices and socially
held beliefs, is not simply at a different level from the individual
experience, but something to which the individual him/herself has
to relate, which the individual him/herself has to experience as an
order which is minimally "reified," externalized. The problem
is therefore not "how to jump from the individual to the social
level?"; the problem is: how should the decentered socio-symbolic
order of institutionalized practices beliefs be structured, if the
subject is to retain his/her "sanity," his/her "normal"
functioning? Which delusions should be deposited there so that individuals
can remain sane? Recall the proverbial egotist, cynically dismissing
the public system of moral norms: as a rule, such a subject can only
function if this system is "out there," publicly recognized,
i.e. in order to be a private cynic, he has to presuppose the existence
of naive other(s) who "really believe." This is how a true
"cultural revolution" should be conducted: not by directly
targeting individuals, endeavouring to "reeducate" them,
to "change their reactionary attitudes," but by depriving
individuals of the support in the "big Other," in the institutional
symbolic order.
When, on the weekend of March 6-7 2001, the Taliban forces in Afghanistan
proceeded to destroy all "idols," especially the two gigantic
Buddha statues carved into the stone at Bamiyan, we got the usual
spectacle of all the "civilized" nations unanimously condemning
the "barbarism" of this act. All the known actors were here:
from the UNICEF expressing concern about the desecration of an important
part of the heritage of humanity, and the New York Metropolitan Museum
offering to buy the statues, up to the Islamic states representatives
and clerics eager to denounce the destruction as contrary to the spirit
of Islam. This kind of protest means strictly NOTHING - it just contributes
to the aseptic liberal (multi)cultural consensus. Instead of hypocritically
bemoaning this destruction, one should rather ask the question: where
do WE stand with regard to faith? Perhaps, therein resides the truly
traumatic dimension of the destruction in Afghanistan: we have here
people who REALLY BELIEVE. After the Taliban government made public
its intention to destroy all statues, most of the Western media first
thought that this is a bluff, part of the strategy to blackmail the
Western powers into recognizing the Taliban regime and pouring the
money into Afghanistan, if they do not execute the announced measure
- now we know they meant it. And it is also not appropriate to compare
this destruction with, say, the demolition of mosques by the Serbs
and Croats in Bosnia a couple of years ago: this destruction was not
a religious act, but a way to strike at the ethnic enemy. Even when,
in European history, Catholics burned Protestant churches and books,
they were trying to annihilate another religious sect. In today's
Afghanistan, on the contrary, there are no non-Muslims, no people
to whom the Buddha statues are sacred objects, so their destruction
is a pure act of annihilation with no roots in any actual ideologico-political
struggles.
In the time of the Chinese Great Cultural Revolution, the Red Guard
gangs were heinously destroying hundreds of monasteries with thousands
of statues and other priceless historical artefacts, their frenetic
activity displaying a desperate endeavor to cut off links with the
reactionary ideological past. Recently, the Chinese strategy underwent
a shift of accent: more than on sheer military coercion, they now
rely on ethnic and economic colonization, rapidly transforming Lhasa
into a Chinese version of the capitalist Wild West, where karaoke
bars intermingle with the Disney-like "Buddhist theme parks"
for the Western tourists. 64What goes on beneath the media image of
the brutal Chinese soldiers and policemen terrorizing the Buddhist
monks conceals is thus the much more effective American-style socioeconomic
transformation: in a decade or two, Tibetans will be reduced to the
status of the native Americans in the USA. Tibetan Buddhism survived
the brutal Red Army onslaught - will it survive the much more artful
economic colonization which, instead of directly attacking the material
manifestations of a belief, undermines its very base, so that, even
if Buddhism survives, it is deprived of its substance, turned into
a simulacrum of itself? So when the Taliban minister of culture said
"We are destroying just stones!", he was in a way right:
for a true Buddhist, the enlightenment/liberation of one single individual
means more than all the statues! The true problem is that the Western
economic-cultural colonization is doing more to undermine the life
style within which Buddhism can thrive than all the Red Guards and
Taliban militias combined: when Red Guards or the Taliban militias
attack, it is still the direct violence and destruction and the struggle
with one unconditional faith against another faith.
The problem with the Taliban regime is elsewhere. The Taliban state
of Afghanistan is the prototypic postmodern state, an exemplary part
of the contemporary global constellation, if there ever was one. First,
its very emergence is the final result of the failure of the Soviet
attempt, in the 70s and 80s, to impose modernization on Afghanistan:
the Taliban movement itself arose out of the religious groups financed
by CIA through Pakistan to fight the Soviet occupation of Afghanistan.
Secondly, if one is to believe the media, the whole economy of Afghanistan
relies on opium: more than two thirds of the world opium crop comes
from Afghanistan, and the Taliban government simply takes the 20%
tax on the farmers' income. The third feature: the Taliban government
does not properly administer social affairs, it just rules. It is
more or less totally indifferent towards of the well-being of its
subjects, relying on the foreign aid or simply ignoring their plight.
"Servicing the goods," guaranteeing the well-being of the
population, is simply not on their agenda - their sole preoccupation
is the imposition of the strict religious order: while economy is
more or less left to itself, the government takes care that all men
have beards, that there are no TV sets and VCRs, that women are fully
covered in public...
Far from being a traditional Islamic regime, the Taliban rule is thus
thoroughly mediated by the process of modernization: relying on the
(paradigmatically modern) split between economy and life-world, it
combines the inclusion into the global market (the opium sales) with
the ideological autarchy. So, paradoxically, we have here a twisted
version of the unconditional Moral Majority rule which turns around
the Western liberal state: instead of a state which limits itself
to guaranteeing the material and institutional conditions for the
well-being, while allowing individuals to pursue their own private
life-styles, the Taliban state is interested ONLY in the life-style,
leaving economy to itself, either to persist at a meager self-subsistence
level or to export opium. In short, the Taliban state is ultimately
nothing but a more radical and brutal version of the Singapore model
of capitalism-cum-Asiatic-values?
Return versus Repetition
The entire history of the Soviet Union can be comprehended as homologous
to Freud's famous image of Rome, a city whose history is deposited
in its present in the guise of the different layers of the archaeological
remainders, each new level covering up the preceding none, like (another
model) the seven layers of Troy, so that history, in its regress towards
ever older epoches, proceeds like the archaeologist, discovering new
layers by probing deeper and deeper into the ground. Was the (official
ideological) history of the Soviet Union not the same accumulation
of exclusions, of turning persons into non-persons, of retroactive
rewriting of history? Quite logically, the "destalinization"
was signalled by the opposite process of "rehabilitation,"
of admitting "errors" in the past politics of the Party.
The gradual "rehabilitation" of the demonized ex-leaders
of the Bolsheviks can thus serve as perhaps the most sensitive index
of how far (and in what direction) the "destalinization"
of the Soviet Union was going. The first to be rehabilitated were
the high military leaders shot in 1937 (Tukhachevsky and others);
the last to be rehabilitated, already in the Gorbachev era, just before
the collapse of the Communist regime, was Bukharin - this last rehabilitation,
of course, was a clear sign of the turn towards capitalism: the Bukharin
which was rehabilitated was the one who, in the 20s, advocated the
pact between workers and peasants (owners of their land), launching
the famous slogan "Get rich!" and opposed forced collectivization.
Significantly, however, one figure was NEVER rehabilitated, excluded
by the Communists as well as by the anti-Communist Russian nationalists:
Trotsky, the "wandering Jew" of the Revolution, the true
anti-Stalin, the arch-enemy, opposing "permanent revolution"
to the idea of "building socialism in one country." One
is tempted to risk here the parallel with Freud's distinction between
primordial (founding) and secondary repression in the Unconscious:
Trotsky's exclusion amounted to something like the "primordial
repression" of the Soviet State, to something which cannot ever
be readmitted through "rehabilitation," since the entire
Order relied on this negative gesture of exclusion. (It is fashionable
to claim that the irony of Stalin's politics from 1928 onwards was
that it effectively WAS a kind of "permanent revolution,"
a permanent state of emergency in which revolution repeatedly devoured
its own children - however, this claim is misleading: the Stalinist
terror is the paradoxical result of the attempt to STABILIZE the Soviet
Union into a state like other, with firm boundaries and institutions,
i.e. terror was a gesture of panic, a defense reaction against the
threat to this State stability.) So Trotsky is the one for whom there
is a place neither in the pre-1990 nor in the post-1990 capitalist
universe in which even the Communist nostalgics don't know what to
do with Trotsky's permanent revolution - perhaps, the signifier "Trotsky"
is the most appropriate designation of that which is worth redeeming
in the Leninist legacy.
The problem with those few remaining orthodox "Leninists"
who behave as if one can simply recycle the old Leninism, continuing
to speak on class struggle, on the betrayal by the corrupted leaders
of the working masses revolutionary impulses, etc., is that it is
not quite clear from which subjective position of enunciation they
speak: they either engage themselves in passionate discussions about
the past (demonstrating with admirable erudition how and where the
anti-Communist "leninologists" falsify Lenin, etc.), in
which case they avoid the question of why (apart from a purely historical
interest) does this matter at all today, or, the closer they get to
contemporary politics, the closer they are to adopting some purely
jargonistic pose which threatens no one. When, in the last months
of 2001, the Milosevic regime in Serbia was finally toppled, I was
asked the same question from my radical friends from the West: "What
about the coal miners whose strike led to the disruption of the electricity
supply and thus effectively brought Milosevic down? Was that not a
genuine workers' movement, which was then manipulated by the politicians,
who were nationalist or corrupted by the CIA?" The same symptomatic
point emerges apropos of every new social upheaval (like the disintegration
of the Real Socialism 10 years ago): in each of these cases, they
identify some working class movement which allegedly displayed a true
revolutionary or, at least, Socialist potential, but was first exploited
and then betrayed by the procapitalist and/or nationalist forces.
This way, one can continue to dream that Revolution is round the corner:
all we need is the authentic leadership which would be able to organize
the workers' revolutionary potentials. If one is to believe them,
Solidarnosc was originally a worker's democratic-socialist movement,
later "betrayed" by being its leadership which was corrupted
by the Church and the CIA... This mysterious working class whose revolutionary
thrust is repeatedly thwarted by the treacherous nationalist and/or
liberal politicians is one of the two fetish of most of the remaining
Trotskyites - the singular point of disavowal which enables them to
sustain their overall interpretation of the state of things. This
fetishist fixation on the old Marxist-Leninist frame is the exact
opposite of the fashionable talk about "new paradigms,"
about how we should leave behind the old "zombie-concepts"
like working class, etc. - the two complementary ways to avoid the
effort to THINK the New which effectively is emerging today. The first
thing to do here is to cancel this disavowal by fully admitting that
this "authentic" working class simply does not exist. (The
other fetish is their belief that things took a bad turn in the Soviet
Union only because Lenin did not succeed in joining forced with Trotsky
in his effort to depose Stalin.) And if we add to this position four
further ones, we get a pretty full picture of the sad predicament
of today's Left: the acceptance of the Cultural Wars (feminist, gay,
anti-racist, etc., multiculturalist struggles) as the dominant terrain
of the emancipatory politics; the purely defensive stance of protecting
the achievements of the Welfare State; the naive belief in cybercommunism
(the idea that the new media are directly creating conditions for
a new authentic community); and, finally, the Third Way, the capitulation
itself. The reference to Lenin should serve as the signifier of the
effort to break the vicious circle of these false options.
John Berger recently made a salient point apropos of a French publicity
poster of the internet investment brokers' company Selftrade: under
the image of a hammer and sickle cast in solid gold and embedded with
diamonds, the caption reads "And if the stock market profited
everybody?" The strategy of this poster is obvious: today, the
stock market fulfills the egalitarian Communist criteria, everybody
can participate in it. Berger indulges in a simple mental experiment:
"Imagine a communications campaign today using an image of a
swastika cast in solid gold and embedded with diamonds! It would of
course not work. Why? The Swastika addressed potential victors not
the defeated. It invoked domination not justice."65 In contrast
to it, the Hammer and Sickle invoked the hope that "history would
eventually be on the side of those struggling for fraternal justice."66
The irony is thus that, at the very moment when this hope is officially
proclaimed dead by the hegemonic ideology of the "end of ideologies,"
a paradigmatically "postindustrial" enterprise (is there
anything more "postindustrial" than dealing with stocks
on the internet?) has to mobilize this dormant hope in order to get
its message through.67 "Repeating Lenin" means giving new
life to this hope which continues to still haunt us.
Consequently, to REPEAT Lenin does NOT mean a RETURN to Lenin - to
repeat Lenin is to accept that "Lenin is dead," that his
particular solution failed, even failed monstrously, but that there
was a utopian spark in it worth saving. 68 To repeat Lenin means that
one has to distinguish between what Lenin effectively did and the
field of possibilities that he opened up, the tension in Lenin between
what he effectively did and another dimension, what was "in Lenin
more than Lenin himself." To repeat Lenin is to repeat not what
Lenin DID, but what he FAILED TO DO, his MISSED opportunities. Today,
Lenin appears as a figure from a different time-zone: it's not that
his notions of the centralized Party, etc., seem to pose a "totalitarian
threat" - it's rather that they seem to belong to a different
epoch to which we can no longer properly relate. However, instead
of reading this fact as the proof that Lenin is outdated, one should,
perhaps, risk the opposite conjecture: what if this impenetrability
of Lenin is a sign that there is something wrong with OUR epoch? What
if the fact that we experience Lenin as irrelevant, "out of sync"
with our postmodern times, impart the much more unsettling message
that our time itself is "out of sync," that a certain historical
dimension is disappearing from it?69 If, to some people, such an assertion
appears dangerously close to the infamous Hegel's quip, when his deduction
why there should be only eight planets circulating around the Sun
was proven wrong by the discovery of the ninth planet (Pluto): "So
much worse for the facts!", then we should be ready to fully
assume this paradox.
How did the ideology of Enlightenment evolve in the 18th century France?
First, there was the epoch of salons, in which philosophers where
trying to shock their benefactors, the generous Counts and Countesses,
even Kings and Emperatrices (Holbach Frederick the Great, Diderot
Catherine the Great), with their "radical" ideas on equality,
the origin of power, the nature of men, etc. - all of this remaining
a kind of intellectual game. At this stage, the idea that someone
could take these ideas literally, as the blueprint for a radical socio-political
transformation, would probably shock the ideologists themselves who
were either part of the entourage of an enlightened nobleman or lone
pathetic figures like Rousseau - their reaction would have been that
of Ivan Karamazov, disgusted upon learning that his bastard half-brother
and servant acted on his nihilistic ruminations, killing his father.
This passage from intellectual game to an idea which effectively "seizes
the masses" is the moment of truth - in it, the intellectual
gets back his own message in its inverted/true form. In France, we
pass from the gentle reflections of Rousseau to the Jacobin Terror;
within the history of Marxism, it is only with Lenin that this passage
occurs, that the games are REALLY over. And it is up to us to repeat
this same passage and accomplish the fateful step from the ludic "postmodern"
radicalism to the domain in which the games are over.
There is an old joke about socialism as the synthesis of the highest
achievements of the entire hitherto human history: from the prehistoric
societies, it took primitivism, from the Ancient world slavery, from
medieval society brutal domination, from capitalism exploitation,
and from socialism the name...70 Does something similar not hold about
our attempt to repeat Lenin's gesture? From the conservative cultural
criticism, it takes the idea that today's democracy is no longer the
place where crucial decisions are made; from cyberspace ideologists
the idea that the global digital network offers a new space of communal
life; etc.etc., and from Lenin more or less just the name itself...
However, this very fact could be turned in an argument FOR the "return
to Lenin": the extent to which the SIGNIFIER "Lenin"
retains its subversive edge is easily demonstrated - say, when one
makes the "Leninist" point that today's democracy is exhausted,
that the key decisions are not taken there, one is directly accused
of "totalitarianism"; when a similar point is made by sociologists
or even Vaclav Havel, they are praised for the depth of their insight...
THIS resistance is the answer to the question "Why Lenin?":
it is the signifier "Lenin" which FORMALIZES this content
found elsewhere, transforming a series of common notions into a truly
subversive theoretical formation.
*
The greatness of Lenin is that he WASN'T AFRAID TO SUCCEED - in contrast
to the negative pathos discernible from Rosa Luxembourg to Adorno,
where the only authentic act is the true failure, the failure which
brings to light the antagonism of the constellation (what, apropos
of Beethoven, Adorno says about the two modes of the artistic failure
- the unauthentic, due simply to the authors subjective deficiency,
and the authentic, which brings to light the limitation of the very
objective social constellation - bears also on his own politics71).
In 1917, instead of waiting for the right moment of maturity, Lenin
organized a preemptive strike; in 1920, finding himself in a position
of the leader of the party of the working class with no working class
(most of it being killed in the civil war), he went on organizing
a state, i.e. he fully accepted the paradox of the party organizing-creating
its base, its working class.
Nowhere is this greatness more palpable than in Lenin's writings of
1917, which cover the span from his initial grasp of the unique revolutionary
chance (first elaborated in the "Letters From Afar") to
the "Letter to Central Committee Members," which finally
convinced the Bolshevik majority that the moment to seize power has
arrived. Everything is here, from "Lenin the ingenious revolutionary
strategist" to "Lenin of the enacted utopia" (of the
immediate abolishing of the state apparatuses). To refer to Kierkegaard,
what we are allowed to perceive in these writings is Lenin-in-becoming:
not yet "Lenin the Soviet institution," but Lenin thrown
into an OPEN situation. Are we, within our late capitalist closure
of the "end of history," still able to experience the shattering
impact of such an authentic historical openness?
ВВЕРХ